In yet a third way, mutual indwelling in the love of
friendship
can be
understood in regard to reciprocal love: inasmuch as friends return
love for love, and both desire and do good things for one another.
understood in regard to reciprocal love: inasmuch as friends return
love for love, and both desire and do good things for one another.
Summa Theologica
ii, 4) that "we love
those who acknowledge their evils. " Therefore it seems that evil is the
cause of love.
Objection 3: Further, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that not "the good"
only but also "the beautiful is beloved by all. "
On the contrary, Augustine says (De Trin. viii, 3): "Assuredly the good
alone is beloved. " Therefore good alone is the cause of love.
I answer that, As stated above ([1229]Q[26], A[1]), Love belongs to the
appetitive power which is a passive faculty. Wherefore its object
stands in relation to it as the cause of its movement or act. Therefore
the cause of love must needs be love's object. Now the proper object of
love is the good; because, as stated above ([1230]Q[26], AA[1],2), love
implies a certain connaturalness or complacency of the lover for the
thing beloved, and to everything, that thing is a good, which is akin
and proportionate to it. It follows, therefore, that good is the proper
cause of love.
Reply to Objection 1: Evil is never loved except under the aspect of
good, that is to say, in so far as it is good in some respect, and is
considered as being good simply. And thus a certain love is evil, in so
far as it tends to that which is not simply a true good. It is in this
way that man "loves iniquity," inasmuch as, by means of iniquity, some
good is gained; pleasure, for instance, or money, or such like.
Reply to Objection 2: Those who acknowledge their evils, are beloved,
not for their evils, but because they acknowledge them, for it is a
good thing to acknowledge one's faults, in so far as it excludes
insincerity or hypocrisy.
Reply to Objection 3: The beautiful is the same as the good, and they
differ in aspect only. For since good is what all seek, the notion of
good is that which calms the desire; while the notion of the beautiful
is that which calms the desire, by being seen or known. Consequently
those senses chiefly regard the beautiful, which are the most
cognitive, viz. sight and hearing, as ministering to reason; for we
speak of beautiful sights and beautiful sounds. But in reference to the
other objects of the other senses, we do not use the expression
"beautiful," for we do not speak of beautiful tastes, and beautiful
odors. Thus it is evident that beauty adds to goodness a relation to
the cognitive faculty: so that "good" means that which simply pleases
the appetite; while the "beautiful" is something pleasant to apprehend.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether knowledge is a cause of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that knowledge is not a cause of love. For
it is due to love that a thing is sought. But some things are sought
without being known, for instance, the sciences; for since "to have
them is the same as to know them," as Augustine says (QQ[83], qu. 35),
if we knew them we should have them, and should not seek them.
Therefore knowledge is not the cause of love.
Objection 2: Further, to love what we know not seems like loving
something more than we know it. But some things are loved more than
they are known: thus in this life God can be loved in Himself, but
cannot be known in Himself. Therefore knowledge is not the cause of
love.
Objection 3: Further, if knowledge were the cause of love, there would
be no love, where there is no knowledge. But in all things there is
love, as Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv); whereas there is not knowledge
in all things. Therefore knowledge is not the cause of love.
On the contrary, Augustine proves (De Trin. x, 1,2) that "none can love
what he does not know. "
I answer that, As stated above [1231](A[1]), good is the cause of love,
as being its object. But good is not the object of the appetite, except
as apprehended. And therefore love demands some apprehension of the
good that is loved. For this reason the Philosopher (Ethic. ix, 5,12)
says that bodily sight is the beginning of sensitive love: and in like
manner the contemplation of spiritual beauty or goodness is the
beginning of spiritual love. Accordingly knowledge is the cause of love
for the same reason as good is, which can be loved only if known.
Reply to Objection 1: He who seeks science, is not entirely without
knowledge thereof: but knows something about it already in some
respect, either in a general way, or in some one of its effects, or
from having heard it commended, as Augustine says (De Trin. x, 1,2).
But to have it is not to know it thus, but to know it perfectly.
Reply to Objection 2: Something is required for the perfection of
knowledge, that is not requisite for the perfection of love. For
knowledge belongs to the reason, whose function it is to distinguish
things which in reality are united, and to unite together, after a
fashion, things that are distinct, by comparing one with another.
Consequently the perfection of knowledge requires that man should know
distinctly all that is in a thing, such as its parts, powers, and
properties. On the other hand, love is in the appetitive power, which
regards a thing as it is in itself: wherefore it suffices, for the
perfection of love, that a thing be loved according as it is known in
itself. Hence it is, therefore, that a thing is loved more than it is
known; since it can be loved perfectly, even without being perfectly
known. This is most evident in regard to the sciences, which some love
through having a certain general knowledge of them: for instance, they
know that rhetoric is a science that enables man to persuade others;
and this is what they love in rhetoric. The same applies to the love of
God.
Reply to Objection 3: Even natural love, which is in all things, is
caused by a kind of knowledge, not indeed existing in natural things
themselves, but in Him Who created their nature, as stated above
(Q[26], A[1]; cf. [1232]FP, Q[6], A[1], ad 2).
__________________________________________________________________
Whether likeness is a cause of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that likeness is not a cause of love. For
the same thing is not the cause of contraries. But likeness is the
cause of hatred; for it is written (Prov. 13:10) that "among the proud
there are always contentions"; and the Philosopher says (Ethic. viii,
1) that "potters quarrel with one another. " Therefore likeness is not a
cause of love.
Objection 2: Further, Augustine says (Confess. iv, 14) that "a man
loves in another that which he would not be himself: thus he loves an
actor, but would not himself be an actor. " But it would not be so, if
likeness were the proper cause of love; for in that case a man would
love in another, that which he possesses himself, or would like to
possess. Therefore likeness is not a cause of love.
Objection 3: Further, everyone loves that which he needs, even if he
have it not: thus a sick man loves health, and a poor man loves riches.
But in so far as he needs them and lacks them, he is unlike them.
Therefore not only likeness but also unlikeness is a cause of love.
Objection 4: Further, the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 4) that "we love
those who bestow money and health on us; and also those who retain
their friendship for the dead. " But all are not such. Therefore
likeness is not a cause of love.
On the contrary, It is written (Ecclus. 13:19): "Every beast loveth its
like. "
I answer that, Likeness, properly speaking, is a cause of love. But it
must be observed that likeness between things is twofold. One kind of
likeness arises from each thing having the same quality actually: for
example, two things possessing the quality of whiteness are said to be
alike. Another kind of likeness arises from one thing having
potentially and by way of inclination, a quality which the other has
actually: thus we may say that a heavy body existing outside its proper
place is like another heavy body that exists in its proper place: or
again, according as potentiality bears a resemblance to its act; since
act is contained, in a manner, in the potentiality itself.
Accordingly the first kind of likeness causes love of friendship or
well-being. For the very fact that two men are alike, having, as it
were, one form, makes them to be, in a manner, one in that form: thus
two men are one thing in the species of humanity, and two white men are
one thing in whiteness. Hence the affections of one tend to the other,
as being one with him; and he wishes good to him as to himself. But the
second kind of likeness causes love of concupiscence, or friendship
founded on usefulness or pleasure: because whatever is in potentiality,
as such, has the desire for its act; and it takes pleasure in its
realization, if it be a sentient and cognitive being.
Now it has been stated above ([1233]Q[26], A[4]), that in the love of
concupiscence, the lover, properly speaking, loves himself, in willing
the good that he desires. But a man loves himself more than another:
because he is one with himself substantially, whereas with another he
is one only in the likeness of some form. Consequently, if this other's
likeness to him arising from the participation of a form, hinders him
from gaining the good that he loves, he becomes hateful to him, not for
being like him, but for hindering him from gaining his own good. This
is why "potters quarrel among themselves," because they hinder one
another's gain: and why "there are contentions among the proud,"
because they hinder one another in attaining the position they covet.
Hence the Reply to the First Objection is evident.
Reply to Objection 2: Even when a man loves in another what he loves
not in himself, there is a certain likeness of proportion: because as
the latter is to that which is loved in him, so is the former to that
which he loves in himself: for instance, if a good singer love a good
writer, we can see a likeness of proportion, inasmuch as each one has
that which is becoming to him in respect of his art.
Reply to Objection 3: He that loves what he needs, bears a likeness to
what he loves, as potentiality bears a likeness to its act, as stated
above.
Reply to Objection 4: According to the same likeness of potentiality to
its act, the illiberal man loves the man who is liberal, in so far as
he expects from him something which he desires. The same applies to the
man who is constant in his friendship as compared to one who is
inconstant. For in either case friendship seems to be based on
usefulness. We might also say that although not all men have these
virtues in the complete habit, yet they have them according to certain
seminal principles in the reason, in force of which principles the man
who is not virtuous loves the virtuous man, as being in conformity with
his own natural reason.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether any other passion of the soul is a cause of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that some other passion can be the cause of
love. For the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 3) says that some are loved for
the sake of the pleasure they give. But pleasure is a passion.
Therefore another passion is a cause of love.
Objection 2: Further, desire is a passion. But we love some because we
desire to receive something from them: as happens in every friendship
based on usefulness. Therefore another passion is a cause of love.
Objection 3: Further, Augustine says (De Trin. x, 1): "When we have no
hope of getting a thing, we love it but half-heartedly or not at all,
even if we see how beautiful it is. " Therefore hope too is a cause of
love.
On the contrary, All the other emotions of the soul are caused by love,
as Augustine says (De Civ. Dei xiv, 7,9).
I answer that, There is no other passion of the soul that does not
presuppose love of some kind. The reason is that every other passion of
the soul implies either movement towards something, or rest in
something. Now every movement towards something, or rest in something,
arises from some kinship or aptness to that thing; and in this does
love consist. Therefore it is not possible for any other passion of the
soul to be universally the cause of every love. But it may happen that
some other passion is the cause of some particular love: just as one
good is the cause of another.
Reply to Objection 1: When a man loves a thing for the pleasure it
affords, his love is indeed caused by pleasure; but that very pleasure
is caused, in its turn, by another preceding love; for none takes
pleasure save in that which is loved in some way.
Reply to Objection 2: Desire for a thing always presupposes love for
that thing. But desire of one thing can be the cause of another thing's
being loved; thus he that desires money, for this reason loves him from
whom he receives it.
Reply to Objection 3: Hope causes or increases love; both by reason of
pleasure, because it causes pleasure; and by reason of desire, because
hope strengthens desire, since we do not desire so intensely that which
we have no hope of receiving. Nevertheless hope itself is of a good
that is loved.
__________________________________________________________________
OF THE EFFECTS OF LOVE (SIX ARTICLES)
We now have to consider the effects of love: under which head there are
six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether union is an effect of love?
(2) Whether mutual indwelling is an effect of love?
(3) Whether ecstasy is an effect of love?
(4) Whether zeal is an effect of love?
(5) Whether love is a passion that is hurtful to the lover?
(6) Whether love is cause of all that the lover does?
__________________________________________________________________
Whether union is an effect of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that union is not an effect of love. For
absence is incompatible with union. But love is compatible with
absence; for the Apostle says (Gal. 4:18): "Be zealous for that which
is good in a good thing always" (speaking of himself, according to a
gloss), "and not only when I am present with you. " Therefore union is
not an effect of love.
Objection 2: Further, every union is either according to essence, thus
form is united to matter, accident to subject, and a part to the whole,
or to another part in order to make up the whole: or according to
likeness, in genus, species, or accident. But love does not cause union
of essence; else love could not be between things essentially distinct.
On the other hand, love does not cause union of likeness, but rather is
caused by it, as stated above ([1234]Q[27], A[3]). Therefore union is
not an effect of love.
Objection 3: Further, the sense in act is the sensible in act, and the
intellect in act is the thing actually understood. But the lover in act
is not the beloved in act. Therefore union is the effect of knowledge
rather than of love.
On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that every love is a
"unitive love. "
I answer that, The union of lover and beloved is twofold. The first is
real union; for instance, when the beloved is present with the lover.
The second is union of affection: and this union must be considered in
relation to the preceding apprehension; since movement of the appetite
follows apprehension. Now love being twofold, viz. love of
concupiscence and love of friendship; each of these arises from a kind
of apprehension of the oneness of the thing loved with the lover. For
when we love a thing, by desiring it, we apprehend it as belonging to
our well-being. In like manner when a man loves another with the love
of friendship, he wills good to him, just as he wills good to himself:
wherefore he apprehends him as his other self, in so far, to wit, as he
wills good to him as to himself. Hence a friend is called a man's
"other self" (Ethic. ix, 4), and Augustine says (Confess. iv, 6), "Well
did one say to his friend: Thou half of my soul. "
The first of these unions is caused "effectively" by love; because love
moves man to desire and seek the presence of the beloved, as of
something suitable and belonging to him. The second union is caused
"formally" by love; because love itself is this union or bond. In this
sense Augustine says (De Trin. viii, 10) that "love is a vital
principle uniting, or seeking to unite two together, the lover, to wit,
and the beloved. " For in describing it as "uniting" he refers to the
union of affection, without which there is no love: and in saying that
"it seeks to unite," he refers to real union.
Reply to Objection 1: This argument is true of real union. That is
necessary to pleasure as being its cause; desire implies the real
absence of the beloved: but love remains whether the beloved be absent
or present.
Reply to Objection 2: Union has a threefold relation to love. There is
union which causes love; and this is substantial union, as regards the
love with which one loves oneself; while as regards the love wherewith
one loves other things, it is the union of likeness, as stated above
([1235]Q[27], A[3]). There is also a union which is essentially love
itself. This union is according to a bond of affection, and is likened
to substantial union, inasmuch as the lover stands to the object of his
love, as to himself, if it be love of friendship; as to something
belonging to himself, if it be love of concupiscence. Again there is a
union, which is the effect of love. This is real union, which the lover
seeks with the object of his love. Moreover this union is in keeping
with the demands of love: for as the Philosopher relates (Polit. ii,
1), "Aristophanes stated that lovers would wish to be united both into
one," but since "this would result in either one or both being
destroyed," they seek a suitable and becoming union---to live together,
speak together, and be united together in other like things.
Reply to Objection 3: Knowledge is perfected by the thing known being
united, through its likeness, to the knower. But the effect of love is
that the thing itself which is loved, is, in a way, united to the
lover, as stated above. Consequently the union caused by love is closer
than that which is caused by knowledge.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether mutual indwelling is an effect of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that love does not cause mutual indwelling,
so that the lover be in the beloved and vice versa. For that which is
in another is contained in it. But the same cannot be container and
contents. Therefore love cannot cause mutual indwelling, so that the
lover be in the beloved and vice versa.
Objection 2: Further, nothing can penetrate within a whole, except by
means of a division of the whole. But it is the function of the reason,
not of the appetite where love resides, to divide things that are
really united. Therefore mutual indwelling is not an effect of love.
Objection 3: Further, if love involves the lover being in the beloved
and vice versa, it follows that the beloved is united to the lover, in
the same way as the lover is united to the beloved. But the union
itself is love, as stated above [1236](A[1]). Therefore it follows that
the lover is always loved by the object of his love; which is evidently
false. Therefore mutual indwelling is not an effect of love.
On the contrary, It is written (1 Jn. 4:16): "He that abideth in
charity abideth in God, and God in him. " Now charity is the love of
God. Therefore, for the same reason, every love makes the beloved to be
in the lover, and vice versa.
I answer that, This effect of mutual indwelling may be understood as
referring both to the apprehensive and to the appetitive power.
Because, as to the apprehensive power, the beloved is said to be in the
lover, inasmuch as the beloved abides in the apprehension of the lover,
according to Phil. 1:7, "For that I have you in my heart": while the
lover is said to be in the beloved, according to apprehension, inasmuch
as the lover is not satisfied with a superficial apprehension of the
beloved, but strives to gain an intimate knowledge of everything
pertaining to the beloved, so as to penetrate into his very soul. Thus
it is written concerning the Holy Ghost, Who is God's Love, that He
"searcheth all things, yea the deep things of God" (1 Cor. 2:10).
As the appetitive power, the object loved is said to be in the lover,
inasmuch as it is in his affections, by a kind of complacency: causing
him either to take pleasure in it, or in its good, when present; or, in
the absence of the object loved, by his longing, to tend towards it
with the love of concupiscence, or towards the good that he wills to
the beloved, with the love of friendship: not indeed from any extrinsic
cause (as when we desire one thing on account of another, or wish good
to another on account of something else), but because the complacency
in the beloved is rooted in the lover's heart. For this reason we speak
of love as being "intimate"; and "of the bowels of charity. " On the
other hand, the lover is in the beloved, by the love of concupiscence
and by the love of friendship, but not in the same way. For the love of
concupiscence is not satisfied with any external or superficial
possession or enjoyment of the beloved; but seeks to possess the
beloved perfectly, by penetrating into his heart, as it were. Whereas,
in the love of friendship, the lover is in the beloved, inasmuch as he
reckons what is good or evil to his friend, as being so to himself; and
his friend's will as his own, so that it seems as though he felt the
good or suffered the evil in the person of his friend. Hence it is
proper to friends "to desire the same things, and to grieve and rejoice
at the same," as the Philosopher says (Ethic. ix, 3 and Rhet. ii, 4).
Consequently in so far as he reckons what affects his friend as
affecting himself, the lover seems to be in the beloved, as though he
were become one with him: but in so far as, on the other hand, he wills
and acts for his friend's sake as for his own sake, looking on his
friend as identified with himself, thus the beloved is in the lover.
In yet a third way, mutual indwelling in the love of friendship can be
understood in regard to reciprocal love: inasmuch as friends return
love for love, and both desire and do good things for one another.
Reply to Objection 1: The beloved is contained in the lover, by being
impressed on his heart and thus becoming the object of his complacency.
On the other hand, the lover is contained in the beloved, inasmuch as
the lover penetrates, so to speak, into the beloved. For nothing
hinders a thing from being both container and contents in different
ways: just as a genus is contained in its species, and vice versa.
Reply to Objection 2: The apprehension of the reason precedes the
movement of love. Consequently, just as the reason divides, so does the
movement of love penetrate into the beloved, as was explained above.
Reply to Objection 3: This argument is true of the third kind of mutual
indwelling, which is not to be found in every kind of love.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether ecstasy is an effect of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that ecstasy is not an effect of love. For
ecstasy seems to imply loss of reason. But love does not always result
in loss of reason: for lovers are masters of themselves at times.
Therefore love does not cause ecstasy.
Objection 2: Further, the lover desires the beloved to be united to
him. Therefore he draws the beloved to himself, rather than betakes
himself into the beloved, going forth out from himself as it were.
Objection 3: Further, love unites the beloved to the lover, as stated
above [1237](A[1]). If, therefore, the lover goes out from himself, in
order to betake himself into the beloved, it follows that the lover
always loves the beloved more than himself: which is evidently false.
Therefore ecstasy is not an effect of love.
On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that "the Divine love
produces ecstasy," and that "God Himself suffered ecstasy through
love. " Since therefore according to the same author (Div. Nom. iv),
every love is a participated likeness of the Divine Love, it seems that
every love causes ecstasy.
I answer that, To suffer ecstasy means to be placed outside oneself.
This happens as to the apprehensive power and as to the appetitive
power. As to the apprehensive power, a man is said to be placed outside
himself, when he is placed outside the knowledge proper to him. This
may be due to his being raised to a higher knowledge; thus, a man is
said to suffer ecstasy, inasmuch as he is placed outside the connatural
apprehension of his sense and reason, when he is raised up so as to
comprehend things that surpass sense and reason: or it may be due to
his being cast down into a state of debasement; thus a man may be said
to suffer ecstasy, when he is overcome by violent passion or madness.
As to the appetitive power, a man is said to suffer ecstasy, when that
power is borne towards something else, so that it goes forth out from
itself, as it were.
The first of these ecstasies is caused by love dispositively in so far,
namely, as love makes the lover dwell on the beloved, as stated above
[1238](A[2]), and to dwell intently on one thing draws the mind from
other things. The second ecstasy is caused by love directly; by love of
friendship, simply; by love of concupiscence not simply but in a
restricted sense. Because in love of concupiscence, the lover is
carried out of himself, in a certain sense; in so far, namely, as not
being satisfied with enjoying the good that he has, he seeks to enjoy
something outside himself. But since he seeks to have this extrinsic
good for himself, he does not go out from himself simply, and this
movement remains finally within him. On the other hand, in the love of
friendship, a man's affection goes out from itself simply; because he
wishes and does good to his friend, by caring and providing for him,
for his sake.
Reply to Objection 1: This argument is true of the first kind of
ecstasy.
Reply to Objection 2: This argument applies to love of concupiscence,
which, as stated above, does not cause ecstasy simply.
Reply to Objection 3: He who loves, goes out from himself, in so far as
he wills the good of his friend and works for it. Yet he does not will
the good of his friend more than his own good: and so it does not
follow that he loves another more than himself.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether zeal is an effect of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that zeal is not an effect of love. For zeal
is a beginning of contention; wherefore it is written (1 Cor. 3:3):
"Whereas there is among you zeal [Douay: 'envying'] and contention,"
etc. But contention is incompatible with love. Therefore zeal is not an
effect of love.
Objection 2: Further, the object of love is the good, which
communicates itself to others. But zeal is opposed to communication;
since it seems an effect of zeal, that a man refuses to share the
object of his love with another: thus husbands are said to be jealous
of [zelare] their wives, because they will not share them with others.
Therefore zeal is not an effect of love.
Objection 3: Further, there is no zeal without hatred, as neither is
there without love: for it is written (Ps. 72:3): "I had a zeal on
occasion of the wicked. " Therefore it should not be set down as an
effect of love any more than of hatred.
On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv): "God is said to be a
zealot, on account of his great love for all things. "
I answer that, Zeal, whatever way we take it, arises from the intensity
of love. For it is evident that the more intensely a power tends to
anything, the more vigorously it withstands opposition or resistance.
Since therefore love is "a movement towards the object loved," as
Augustine says (QQ. 83, qu. 35), an intense love seeks to remove
everything that opposes it.
But this happens in different ways according to love of concupiscence,
and love of friendship. For in love of concupiscence he who desires
something intensely, is moved against all that hinders his gaining or
quietly enjoying the object of his love. It is thus that husbands are
said to be jealous of their wives, lest association with others prove a
hindrance to their exclusive individual rights. In like manner those
who seek to excel, are moved against those who seem to excel, as though
these were a hindrance to their excelling. And this is the zeal of
envy, of which it is written (Ps. 36:1): "Be not emulous of evil doers,
nor envy [zelaveris] them that work iniquity. "
On the other hand, love of friendship seeks the friend's good:
wherefore, when it is intense, it causes a man to be moved against
everything that opposes the friend's good. In this respect, a man is
said to be zealous on behalf of his friend, when he makes a point of
repelling whatever may be said or done against the friend's good. In
this way, too, a man is said to be zealous on God's behalf, when he
endeavors, to the best of his means, to repel whatever is contrary to
the honor or will of God; according to 3 Kings 19:14: "With zeal I have
been zealous for the Lord of hosts. " Again on the words of Jn. 2:17:
"The zeal of Thy house hath eaten me up," a gloss says that "a man is
eaten up with a good zeal, who strives to remedy whatever evil he
perceives; and if he cannot, bears with it and laments it. "
Reply to Objection 1: The Apostle is speaking in this passage of the
zeal of envy; which is indeed the cause of contention, not against the
object of love, but for it, and against that which is opposed to it.
Reply to Objection 2: Good is loved inasmuch as it can be communicated
to the lover. Consequently whatever hinders the perfection of this
communication, becomes hateful. Thus zeal arises from love of good. But
through defect of goodness, it happens that certain small goods cannot,
in their entirety, be possessed by many at the same time: and from the
love of such things arises the zeal of envy. But it does not arise,
properly speaking, in the case of those things which, in their
entirety, can be possessed by many: for no one envies another the
knowledge of truth, which can be known entirely by many; except perhaps
one may envy another his superiority in the knowledge of it.
Reply to Objection 3: The very fact that a man hates whatever is
opposed to the object of his love, is the effect of love. Hence zeal is
set down as an effect of love rather than of hatred.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether love is a passion that wounds the lover?
Objection 1: It would seem that love wounds the lover. For languor
denotes a hurt in the one that languishes. But love causes languor: for
it is written (Cant 2:5): "Stay me up with flowers, compass me about
with apples; because I languish with love. " Therefore love is a
wounding passion.
Objection 2: Further, melting is a kind of dissolution. But love melts
that in which it is: for it is written (Cant 5:6): "My soul melted when
my beloved spoke. " Therefore love is a dissolvent: therefore it is a
corruptive and a wounding passion.
Objection 3: Further, fervor denotes a certain excess of heat; which
excess has a corruptive effect. But love causes fervor: for Dionysius
(Coel. Hier. vii) in reckoning the properties belonging to the
Seraphim's love, includes "hot" and "piercing" and "most fervent. "
Moreover it is said of love (Cant 8:6) that "its lamps are fire and
flames. " Therefore love is a wounding and corruptive passion.
On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that "everything loves
itself with a love that holds it together," i. e. that preserves it.
Therefore love is not a wounding passion, but rather one that preserves
and perfects.
I answer that, As stated above ([1239]Q[26], AA[1],2;[1240] Q[27],
A[1]), love denotes a certain adapting of the appetitive power to some
good. Now nothing is hurt by being adapted to that which is suitable to
it; rather, if possible, it is perfected and bettered. But if a thing
be adapted to that which is not suitable to it, it is hurt and made
worse thereby. Consequently love of a suitable good perfects and
betters the lover; but love of a good which is unsuitable to the lover,
wounds and worsens him. Wherefore man is perfected and bettered chiefly
by the love of God: but is wounded and worsened by the love of sin,
according to Osee 9:10: "They became abominable, as those things which
they loved. "
And let this be understood as applying to love in respect of its formal
element, i. e. in regard to the appetite. But in respect of the material
element in the passion of love, i. e. a certain bodily change, it
happens that love is hurtful, by reason of this change being excessive:
just as it happens in the senses, and in every act of a power of the
soul that is exercised through the change of some bodily organ.
In reply to the objections, it is to be observed that four proximate
effects may be ascribed to love: viz. melting, enjoyment, languor, and
fervor. Of these the first is "melting," which is opposed to freezing.
For things that are frozen, are closely bound together, so as to be
hard to pierce. But it belongs to love that the appetite is fitted to
receive the good which is loved, inasmuch as the object loved is in the
lover, as stated above [1241](A[2]). Consequently the freezing or
hardening of the heart is a disposition incompatible with love: while
melting denotes a softening of the heart, whereby the heart shows
itself to be ready for the entrance of the beloved. If, then, the
beloved is present and possessed, pleasure or enjoyment ensues. But if
the beloved be absent, two passions arise; viz. sadness at its absence,
which is denoted by "languor" (hence Cicero in De Tusc. Quaest. iii, 11
applies the term "ailment" chiefly to sadness); and an intense desire
to possess the beloved, which is signified by "fervor. " And these are
the effects of love considered formally, according to the relation of
the appetitive power to its object. But in the passion of love, other
effects ensue, proportionate to the above, in respect of a change in
the organ.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether love is cause of all that the lover does?
Objection 1: It would seem that the lover does not do everything from
love. For love is a passion, as stated above ([1242]Q[26], A[2]). But
man does not do everything from passion: but some things he does from
choice, and some things from ignorance, as stated in Ethic. v, 8.
Therefore not everything that a man does, is done from love.
Objection 2: Further, the appetite is a principle of movement and
action in all animals, as stated in De Anima iii, 10. If, therefore,
whatever a man does is done from love, the other passions of the
appetitive faculty are superfluous.
Objection 3: Further, nothing is produced at one and the same time by
contrary causes. But some things are done from hatred. Therefore all
things are not done from love.
On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that "all things,
whatever they do, they do for the love of good. "
I answer that, Every agent acts for an end, as stated above
([1243]Q[1], A[2] ). Now the end is the good desired and loved by each
one. Wherefore it is evident that every agent, whatever it be, does
every action from love of some kind.
Reply to Objection 1: This objection takes love as a passion existing
in the sensitive appetite. But here we are speaking of love in a
general sense, inasmuch as it includes intellectual, rational, animal,
and natural love: for it is in this sense that Dionysius speaks of love
in chapter iv of De Divinis Nominibus.
Reply to Objection 2: As stated above [1244](A[5]; Q[27], A[4]) desire,
sadness and pleasure, and consequently all the other passions of the
soul, result from love. Wherefore every act proceeds from any passion,
proceeds also from love as from a first cause: and so the other
passions, which are proximate causes, are not superfluous.
Reply to Objection 3: Hatred also is a result of love, as we shall
state further on ([1245]Q[29], A[2]).
__________________________________________________________________
OF HATRED (SIX ARTICLES)
We must now consider hatred: concerning which there are six points of
inquiry:
(1) Whether evil is the cause and the object of hatred?
(2) Whether love is the cause of hatred?
(3) Whether hatred is stronger than love?
(4) Whether a man can hate himself?
(5) Whether a man can hate the truth?
(6) Whether a thing can be the object of universal hatred?
__________________________________________________________________
Whether evil is the cause and object of hatred?
Objection 1: It would seem that evil is not the object and cause of
hatred. For everything that exists, as such, is good. If therefore evil
be the object of hatred, it follows that nothing but the lack of
something can be the object of hatred: which is clearly untrue.
Objection 2: Further, hatred of evil is praise-worthy; hence (2 Macc
3:1) some are praised for that "the laws were very well kept, because
of the godliness of Onias the high-priest, and the hatred of their
souls [Douay: 'his soul'] had no evil. " If, therefore, nothing but evil
be the object of hatred, it would follow that all hatred is
commendable: and this is clearly false.
Objection 3: Further, the same thing is not at the same time both good
and evil. But the same thing is lovable and hateful to different
subjects. Therefore hatred is not only of evil, but also of good.
On the contrary, Hatred is the opposite of love. But the object of love
is good, as stated above ([1246]Q[26], A[1];[1247] Q[27], A[1]).
Therefore the object of hatred is evil.
I answer that, Since the natural appetite is the result of apprehension
(though this apprehension is not in the same subject as the natural
appetite), it seems that what applies to the inclination of the natural
appetite, applies also to the animal appetite, which does result from
an apprehension in the same subject, as stated above ([1248]Q[26],
A[1]). Now, with regard to the natural appetite, it is evident, that
just as each thing is naturally attuned and adapted to that which is
suitable to it, wherein consists natural love; so has it a natural
dissonance from that which opposes and destroys it; and this is natural
hatred. So, therefore, in the animal appetite, or in the intellectual
appetite, love is a certain harmony of the appetite with that which is
apprehended as suitable; while hatred is dissonance of the appetite
from that which is apprehended as repugnant and hurtful. Now, just as
whatever is suitable, as such, bears the aspect of good; so whatever is
repugnant, as such, bears the aspect of evil. And therefore, just as
good is the object of love, so evil is the object of hatred.
Reply to Objection 1: Being, as such, has not the aspect of repugnance
but only of fittingness; because being is common to all things. But
being, inasmuch as it is this determinate being, has an aspect of
repugnance to some determinate being. And in this way, one being is
hateful to another, and is evil; though not in itself, but by
comparison with something else.
Reply to Objection 2: Just as a thing may be apprehended as good, when
it is not truly good; so a thing may be apprehended as evil, whereas it
is not truly evil. Hence it happens sometimes that neither hatred of
evil nor love of good is good.
Reply to Objection 3: To different things the same thing may be lovable
or hateful: in respect of the natural appetite, owing to one and the
same thing being naturally suitable to one thing, and naturally
unsuitable to another: thus heat is becoming to fire and unbecoming to
water: and in respect of the animal appetite, owing to one and the same
thing being apprehended by one as good, by another as bad.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether love is a cause of hatred?
Objection 1: It would seem that love is not a cause of hatred. For "the
opposite members of a division are naturally simultaneous" (Praedic.
x). But love and hatred are opposite members of a division, since they
are contrary to one another. Therefore they are naturally simultaneous.
Therefore love is not the cause of hatred.
Objection 2: Further, of two contraries, one is not the cause of the
other. But love and hatred are contraries. Therefore love is not the
cause of hatred.
Objection 3: Further, that which follows is not the cause of that which
precedes. But hatred precedes love, seemingly: since hatred implies a
turning away from evil, whereas love implies a turning towards good.
Therefore love is not the cause of hatred.
On the contrary, Augustine says (De Civ. Dei xiv, 7,9) that all
emotions are caused by love. Therefore hatred also, since it is an
emotion of the soul, is caused by love.
I answer that, As stated above [1249](A[1]), love consists in a certain
agreement of the lover with the object loved, while hatred consists in
a certain disagreement or dissonance. Now we should consider in each
thing, what agrees with it, before that which disagrees: since a thing
disagrees with another, through destroying or hindering that which
agrees with it. Consequently love must needs precede hatred; and
nothing is hated, save through being contrary to a suitable thing which
is loved. And hence it is that every hatred is caused by love.
Reply to Objection 1: The opposite members of a division are sometimes
naturally simultaneous, both really and logically; e. g. two species of
animal, or two species of color. Sometimes they are simultaneous
logically, while, in reality, one precedes, and causes the other; e. g.
the species of numbers, figures and movements. Sometimes they are not
simultaneous either really or logically; e. g. substance and accident;
for substance is in reality the cause of accident; and being is
predicated of substance before it is predicated of accident, by a
priority of reason, because it is not predicated of accident except
inasmuch as the latter is in substance. Now love and hatred are
naturally simultaneous, logically but not really.
those who acknowledge their evils. " Therefore it seems that evil is the
cause of love.
Objection 3: Further, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that not "the good"
only but also "the beautiful is beloved by all. "
On the contrary, Augustine says (De Trin. viii, 3): "Assuredly the good
alone is beloved. " Therefore good alone is the cause of love.
I answer that, As stated above ([1229]Q[26], A[1]), Love belongs to the
appetitive power which is a passive faculty. Wherefore its object
stands in relation to it as the cause of its movement or act. Therefore
the cause of love must needs be love's object. Now the proper object of
love is the good; because, as stated above ([1230]Q[26], AA[1],2), love
implies a certain connaturalness or complacency of the lover for the
thing beloved, and to everything, that thing is a good, which is akin
and proportionate to it. It follows, therefore, that good is the proper
cause of love.
Reply to Objection 1: Evil is never loved except under the aspect of
good, that is to say, in so far as it is good in some respect, and is
considered as being good simply. And thus a certain love is evil, in so
far as it tends to that which is not simply a true good. It is in this
way that man "loves iniquity," inasmuch as, by means of iniquity, some
good is gained; pleasure, for instance, or money, or such like.
Reply to Objection 2: Those who acknowledge their evils, are beloved,
not for their evils, but because they acknowledge them, for it is a
good thing to acknowledge one's faults, in so far as it excludes
insincerity or hypocrisy.
Reply to Objection 3: The beautiful is the same as the good, and they
differ in aspect only. For since good is what all seek, the notion of
good is that which calms the desire; while the notion of the beautiful
is that which calms the desire, by being seen or known. Consequently
those senses chiefly regard the beautiful, which are the most
cognitive, viz. sight and hearing, as ministering to reason; for we
speak of beautiful sights and beautiful sounds. But in reference to the
other objects of the other senses, we do not use the expression
"beautiful," for we do not speak of beautiful tastes, and beautiful
odors. Thus it is evident that beauty adds to goodness a relation to
the cognitive faculty: so that "good" means that which simply pleases
the appetite; while the "beautiful" is something pleasant to apprehend.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether knowledge is a cause of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that knowledge is not a cause of love. For
it is due to love that a thing is sought. But some things are sought
without being known, for instance, the sciences; for since "to have
them is the same as to know them," as Augustine says (QQ[83], qu. 35),
if we knew them we should have them, and should not seek them.
Therefore knowledge is not the cause of love.
Objection 2: Further, to love what we know not seems like loving
something more than we know it. But some things are loved more than
they are known: thus in this life God can be loved in Himself, but
cannot be known in Himself. Therefore knowledge is not the cause of
love.
Objection 3: Further, if knowledge were the cause of love, there would
be no love, where there is no knowledge. But in all things there is
love, as Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv); whereas there is not knowledge
in all things. Therefore knowledge is not the cause of love.
On the contrary, Augustine proves (De Trin. x, 1,2) that "none can love
what he does not know. "
I answer that, As stated above [1231](A[1]), good is the cause of love,
as being its object. But good is not the object of the appetite, except
as apprehended. And therefore love demands some apprehension of the
good that is loved. For this reason the Philosopher (Ethic. ix, 5,12)
says that bodily sight is the beginning of sensitive love: and in like
manner the contemplation of spiritual beauty or goodness is the
beginning of spiritual love. Accordingly knowledge is the cause of love
for the same reason as good is, which can be loved only if known.
Reply to Objection 1: He who seeks science, is not entirely without
knowledge thereof: but knows something about it already in some
respect, either in a general way, or in some one of its effects, or
from having heard it commended, as Augustine says (De Trin. x, 1,2).
But to have it is not to know it thus, but to know it perfectly.
Reply to Objection 2: Something is required for the perfection of
knowledge, that is not requisite for the perfection of love. For
knowledge belongs to the reason, whose function it is to distinguish
things which in reality are united, and to unite together, after a
fashion, things that are distinct, by comparing one with another.
Consequently the perfection of knowledge requires that man should know
distinctly all that is in a thing, such as its parts, powers, and
properties. On the other hand, love is in the appetitive power, which
regards a thing as it is in itself: wherefore it suffices, for the
perfection of love, that a thing be loved according as it is known in
itself. Hence it is, therefore, that a thing is loved more than it is
known; since it can be loved perfectly, even without being perfectly
known. This is most evident in regard to the sciences, which some love
through having a certain general knowledge of them: for instance, they
know that rhetoric is a science that enables man to persuade others;
and this is what they love in rhetoric. The same applies to the love of
God.
Reply to Objection 3: Even natural love, which is in all things, is
caused by a kind of knowledge, not indeed existing in natural things
themselves, but in Him Who created their nature, as stated above
(Q[26], A[1]; cf. [1232]FP, Q[6], A[1], ad 2).
__________________________________________________________________
Whether likeness is a cause of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that likeness is not a cause of love. For
the same thing is not the cause of contraries. But likeness is the
cause of hatred; for it is written (Prov. 13:10) that "among the proud
there are always contentions"; and the Philosopher says (Ethic. viii,
1) that "potters quarrel with one another. " Therefore likeness is not a
cause of love.
Objection 2: Further, Augustine says (Confess. iv, 14) that "a man
loves in another that which he would not be himself: thus he loves an
actor, but would not himself be an actor. " But it would not be so, if
likeness were the proper cause of love; for in that case a man would
love in another, that which he possesses himself, or would like to
possess. Therefore likeness is not a cause of love.
Objection 3: Further, everyone loves that which he needs, even if he
have it not: thus a sick man loves health, and a poor man loves riches.
But in so far as he needs them and lacks them, he is unlike them.
Therefore not only likeness but also unlikeness is a cause of love.
Objection 4: Further, the Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 4) that "we love
those who bestow money and health on us; and also those who retain
their friendship for the dead. " But all are not such. Therefore
likeness is not a cause of love.
On the contrary, It is written (Ecclus. 13:19): "Every beast loveth its
like. "
I answer that, Likeness, properly speaking, is a cause of love. But it
must be observed that likeness between things is twofold. One kind of
likeness arises from each thing having the same quality actually: for
example, two things possessing the quality of whiteness are said to be
alike. Another kind of likeness arises from one thing having
potentially and by way of inclination, a quality which the other has
actually: thus we may say that a heavy body existing outside its proper
place is like another heavy body that exists in its proper place: or
again, according as potentiality bears a resemblance to its act; since
act is contained, in a manner, in the potentiality itself.
Accordingly the first kind of likeness causes love of friendship or
well-being. For the very fact that two men are alike, having, as it
were, one form, makes them to be, in a manner, one in that form: thus
two men are one thing in the species of humanity, and two white men are
one thing in whiteness. Hence the affections of one tend to the other,
as being one with him; and he wishes good to him as to himself. But the
second kind of likeness causes love of concupiscence, or friendship
founded on usefulness or pleasure: because whatever is in potentiality,
as such, has the desire for its act; and it takes pleasure in its
realization, if it be a sentient and cognitive being.
Now it has been stated above ([1233]Q[26], A[4]), that in the love of
concupiscence, the lover, properly speaking, loves himself, in willing
the good that he desires. But a man loves himself more than another:
because he is one with himself substantially, whereas with another he
is one only in the likeness of some form. Consequently, if this other's
likeness to him arising from the participation of a form, hinders him
from gaining the good that he loves, he becomes hateful to him, not for
being like him, but for hindering him from gaining his own good. This
is why "potters quarrel among themselves," because they hinder one
another's gain: and why "there are contentions among the proud,"
because they hinder one another in attaining the position they covet.
Hence the Reply to the First Objection is evident.
Reply to Objection 2: Even when a man loves in another what he loves
not in himself, there is a certain likeness of proportion: because as
the latter is to that which is loved in him, so is the former to that
which he loves in himself: for instance, if a good singer love a good
writer, we can see a likeness of proportion, inasmuch as each one has
that which is becoming to him in respect of his art.
Reply to Objection 3: He that loves what he needs, bears a likeness to
what he loves, as potentiality bears a likeness to its act, as stated
above.
Reply to Objection 4: According to the same likeness of potentiality to
its act, the illiberal man loves the man who is liberal, in so far as
he expects from him something which he desires. The same applies to the
man who is constant in his friendship as compared to one who is
inconstant. For in either case friendship seems to be based on
usefulness. We might also say that although not all men have these
virtues in the complete habit, yet they have them according to certain
seminal principles in the reason, in force of which principles the man
who is not virtuous loves the virtuous man, as being in conformity with
his own natural reason.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether any other passion of the soul is a cause of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that some other passion can be the cause of
love. For the Philosopher (Ethic. viii, 3) says that some are loved for
the sake of the pleasure they give. But pleasure is a passion.
Therefore another passion is a cause of love.
Objection 2: Further, desire is a passion. But we love some because we
desire to receive something from them: as happens in every friendship
based on usefulness. Therefore another passion is a cause of love.
Objection 3: Further, Augustine says (De Trin. x, 1): "When we have no
hope of getting a thing, we love it but half-heartedly or not at all,
even if we see how beautiful it is. " Therefore hope too is a cause of
love.
On the contrary, All the other emotions of the soul are caused by love,
as Augustine says (De Civ. Dei xiv, 7,9).
I answer that, There is no other passion of the soul that does not
presuppose love of some kind. The reason is that every other passion of
the soul implies either movement towards something, or rest in
something. Now every movement towards something, or rest in something,
arises from some kinship or aptness to that thing; and in this does
love consist. Therefore it is not possible for any other passion of the
soul to be universally the cause of every love. But it may happen that
some other passion is the cause of some particular love: just as one
good is the cause of another.
Reply to Objection 1: When a man loves a thing for the pleasure it
affords, his love is indeed caused by pleasure; but that very pleasure
is caused, in its turn, by another preceding love; for none takes
pleasure save in that which is loved in some way.
Reply to Objection 2: Desire for a thing always presupposes love for
that thing. But desire of one thing can be the cause of another thing's
being loved; thus he that desires money, for this reason loves him from
whom he receives it.
Reply to Objection 3: Hope causes or increases love; both by reason of
pleasure, because it causes pleasure; and by reason of desire, because
hope strengthens desire, since we do not desire so intensely that which
we have no hope of receiving. Nevertheless hope itself is of a good
that is loved.
__________________________________________________________________
OF THE EFFECTS OF LOVE (SIX ARTICLES)
We now have to consider the effects of love: under which head there are
six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether union is an effect of love?
(2) Whether mutual indwelling is an effect of love?
(3) Whether ecstasy is an effect of love?
(4) Whether zeal is an effect of love?
(5) Whether love is a passion that is hurtful to the lover?
(6) Whether love is cause of all that the lover does?
__________________________________________________________________
Whether union is an effect of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that union is not an effect of love. For
absence is incompatible with union. But love is compatible with
absence; for the Apostle says (Gal. 4:18): "Be zealous for that which
is good in a good thing always" (speaking of himself, according to a
gloss), "and not only when I am present with you. " Therefore union is
not an effect of love.
Objection 2: Further, every union is either according to essence, thus
form is united to matter, accident to subject, and a part to the whole,
or to another part in order to make up the whole: or according to
likeness, in genus, species, or accident. But love does not cause union
of essence; else love could not be between things essentially distinct.
On the other hand, love does not cause union of likeness, but rather is
caused by it, as stated above ([1234]Q[27], A[3]). Therefore union is
not an effect of love.
Objection 3: Further, the sense in act is the sensible in act, and the
intellect in act is the thing actually understood. But the lover in act
is not the beloved in act. Therefore union is the effect of knowledge
rather than of love.
On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that every love is a
"unitive love. "
I answer that, The union of lover and beloved is twofold. The first is
real union; for instance, when the beloved is present with the lover.
The second is union of affection: and this union must be considered in
relation to the preceding apprehension; since movement of the appetite
follows apprehension. Now love being twofold, viz. love of
concupiscence and love of friendship; each of these arises from a kind
of apprehension of the oneness of the thing loved with the lover. For
when we love a thing, by desiring it, we apprehend it as belonging to
our well-being. In like manner when a man loves another with the love
of friendship, he wills good to him, just as he wills good to himself:
wherefore he apprehends him as his other self, in so far, to wit, as he
wills good to him as to himself. Hence a friend is called a man's
"other self" (Ethic. ix, 4), and Augustine says (Confess. iv, 6), "Well
did one say to his friend: Thou half of my soul. "
The first of these unions is caused "effectively" by love; because love
moves man to desire and seek the presence of the beloved, as of
something suitable and belonging to him. The second union is caused
"formally" by love; because love itself is this union or bond. In this
sense Augustine says (De Trin. viii, 10) that "love is a vital
principle uniting, or seeking to unite two together, the lover, to wit,
and the beloved. " For in describing it as "uniting" he refers to the
union of affection, without which there is no love: and in saying that
"it seeks to unite," he refers to real union.
Reply to Objection 1: This argument is true of real union. That is
necessary to pleasure as being its cause; desire implies the real
absence of the beloved: but love remains whether the beloved be absent
or present.
Reply to Objection 2: Union has a threefold relation to love. There is
union which causes love; and this is substantial union, as regards the
love with which one loves oneself; while as regards the love wherewith
one loves other things, it is the union of likeness, as stated above
([1235]Q[27], A[3]). There is also a union which is essentially love
itself. This union is according to a bond of affection, and is likened
to substantial union, inasmuch as the lover stands to the object of his
love, as to himself, if it be love of friendship; as to something
belonging to himself, if it be love of concupiscence. Again there is a
union, which is the effect of love. This is real union, which the lover
seeks with the object of his love. Moreover this union is in keeping
with the demands of love: for as the Philosopher relates (Polit. ii,
1), "Aristophanes stated that lovers would wish to be united both into
one," but since "this would result in either one or both being
destroyed," they seek a suitable and becoming union---to live together,
speak together, and be united together in other like things.
Reply to Objection 3: Knowledge is perfected by the thing known being
united, through its likeness, to the knower. But the effect of love is
that the thing itself which is loved, is, in a way, united to the
lover, as stated above. Consequently the union caused by love is closer
than that which is caused by knowledge.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether mutual indwelling is an effect of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that love does not cause mutual indwelling,
so that the lover be in the beloved and vice versa. For that which is
in another is contained in it. But the same cannot be container and
contents. Therefore love cannot cause mutual indwelling, so that the
lover be in the beloved and vice versa.
Objection 2: Further, nothing can penetrate within a whole, except by
means of a division of the whole. But it is the function of the reason,
not of the appetite where love resides, to divide things that are
really united. Therefore mutual indwelling is not an effect of love.
Objection 3: Further, if love involves the lover being in the beloved
and vice versa, it follows that the beloved is united to the lover, in
the same way as the lover is united to the beloved. But the union
itself is love, as stated above [1236](A[1]). Therefore it follows that
the lover is always loved by the object of his love; which is evidently
false. Therefore mutual indwelling is not an effect of love.
On the contrary, It is written (1 Jn. 4:16): "He that abideth in
charity abideth in God, and God in him. " Now charity is the love of
God. Therefore, for the same reason, every love makes the beloved to be
in the lover, and vice versa.
I answer that, This effect of mutual indwelling may be understood as
referring both to the apprehensive and to the appetitive power.
Because, as to the apprehensive power, the beloved is said to be in the
lover, inasmuch as the beloved abides in the apprehension of the lover,
according to Phil. 1:7, "For that I have you in my heart": while the
lover is said to be in the beloved, according to apprehension, inasmuch
as the lover is not satisfied with a superficial apprehension of the
beloved, but strives to gain an intimate knowledge of everything
pertaining to the beloved, so as to penetrate into his very soul. Thus
it is written concerning the Holy Ghost, Who is God's Love, that He
"searcheth all things, yea the deep things of God" (1 Cor. 2:10).
As the appetitive power, the object loved is said to be in the lover,
inasmuch as it is in his affections, by a kind of complacency: causing
him either to take pleasure in it, or in its good, when present; or, in
the absence of the object loved, by his longing, to tend towards it
with the love of concupiscence, or towards the good that he wills to
the beloved, with the love of friendship: not indeed from any extrinsic
cause (as when we desire one thing on account of another, or wish good
to another on account of something else), but because the complacency
in the beloved is rooted in the lover's heart. For this reason we speak
of love as being "intimate"; and "of the bowels of charity. " On the
other hand, the lover is in the beloved, by the love of concupiscence
and by the love of friendship, but not in the same way. For the love of
concupiscence is not satisfied with any external or superficial
possession or enjoyment of the beloved; but seeks to possess the
beloved perfectly, by penetrating into his heart, as it were. Whereas,
in the love of friendship, the lover is in the beloved, inasmuch as he
reckons what is good or evil to his friend, as being so to himself; and
his friend's will as his own, so that it seems as though he felt the
good or suffered the evil in the person of his friend. Hence it is
proper to friends "to desire the same things, and to grieve and rejoice
at the same," as the Philosopher says (Ethic. ix, 3 and Rhet. ii, 4).
Consequently in so far as he reckons what affects his friend as
affecting himself, the lover seems to be in the beloved, as though he
were become one with him: but in so far as, on the other hand, he wills
and acts for his friend's sake as for his own sake, looking on his
friend as identified with himself, thus the beloved is in the lover.
In yet a third way, mutual indwelling in the love of friendship can be
understood in regard to reciprocal love: inasmuch as friends return
love for love, and both desire and do good things for one another.
Reply to Objection 1: The beloved is contained in the lover, by being
impressed on his heart and thus becoming the object of his complacency.
On the other hand, the lover is contained in the beloved, inasmuch as
the lover penetrates, so to speak, into the beloved. For nothing
hinders a thing from being both container and contents in different
ways: just as a genus is contained in its species, and vice versa.
Reply to Objection 2: The apprehension of the reason precedes the
movement of love. Consequently, just as the reason divides, so does the
movement of love penetrate into the beloved, as was explained above.
Reply to Objection 3: This argument is true of the third kind of mutual
indwelling, which is not to be found in every kind of love.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether ecstasy is an effect of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that ecstasy is not an effect of love. For
ecstasy seems to imply loss of reason. But love does not always result
in loss of reason: for lovers are masters of themselves at times.
Therefore love does not cause ecstasy.
Objection 2: Further, the lover desires the beloved to be united to
him. Therefore he draws the beloved to himself, rather than betakes
himself into the beloved, going forth out from himself as it were.
Objection 3: Further, love unites the beloved to the lover, as stated
above [1237](A[1]). If, therefore, the lover goes out from himself, in
order to betake himself into the beloved, it follows that the lover
always loves the beloved more than himself: which is evidently false.
Therefore ecstasy is not an effect of love.
On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that "the Divine love
produces ecstasy," and that "God Himself suffered ecstasy through
love. " Since therefore according to the same author (Div. Nom. iv),
every love is a participated likeness of the Divine Love, it seems that
every love causes ecstasy.
I answer that, To suffer ecstasy means to be placed outside oneself.
This happens as to the apprehensive power and as to the appetitive
power. As to the apprehensive power, a man is said to be placed outside
himself, when he is placed outside the knowledge proper to him. This
may be due to his being raised to a higher knowledge; thus, a man is
said to suffer ecstasy, inasmuch as he is placed outside the connatural
apprehension of his sense and reason, when he is raised up so as to
comprehend things that surpass sense and reason: or it may be due to
his being cast down into a state of debasement; thus a man may be said
to suffer ecstasy, when he is overcome by violent passion or madness.
As to the appetitive power, a man is said to suffer ecstasy, when that
power is borne towards something else, so that it goes forth out from
itself, as it were.
The first of these ecstasies is caused by love dispositively in so far,
namely, as love makes the lover dwell on the beloved, as stated above
[1238](A[2]), and to dwell intently on one thing draws the mind from
other things. The second ecstasy is caused by love directly; by love of
friendship, simply; by love of concupiscence not simply but in a
restricted sense. Because in love of concupiscence, the lover is
carried out of himself, in a certain sense; in so far, namely, as not
being satisfied with enjoying the good that he has, he seeks to enjoy
something outside himself. But since he seeks to have this extrinsic
good for himself, he does not go out from himself simply, and this
movement remains finally within him. On the other hand, in the love of
friendship, a man's affection goes out from itself simply; because he
wishes and does good to his friend, by caring and providing for him,
for his sake.
Reply to Objection 1: This argument is true of the first kind of
ecstasy.
Reply to Objection 2: This argument applies to love of concupiscence,
which, as stated above, does not cause ecstasy simply.
Reply to Objection 3: He who loves, goes out from himself, in so far as
he wills the good of his friend and works for it. Yet he does not will
the good of his friend more than his own good: and so it does not
follow that he loves another more than himself.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether zeal is an effect of love?
Objection 1: It would seem that zeal is not an effect of love. For zeal
is a beginning of contention; wherefore it is written (1 Cor. 3:3):
"Whereas there is among you zeal [Douay: 'envying'] and contention,"
etc. But contention is incompatible with love. Therefore zeal is not an
effect of love.
Objection 2: Further, the object of love is the good, which
communicates itself to others. But zeal is opposed to communication;
since it seems an effect of zeal, that a man refuses to share the
object of his love with another: thus husbands are said to be jealous
of [zelare] their wives, because they will not share them with others.
Therefore zeal is not an effect of love.
Objection 3: Further, there is no zeal without hatred, as neither is
there without love: for it is written (Ps. 72:3): "I had a zeal on
occasion of the wicked. " Therefore it should not be set down as an
effect of love any more than of hatred.
On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv): "God is said to be a
zealot, on account of his great love for all things. "
I answer that, Zeal, whatever way we take it, arises from the intensity
of love. For it is evident that the more intensely a power tends to
anything, the more vigorously it withstands opposition or resistance.
Since therefore love is "a movement towards the object loved," as
Augustine says (QQ. 83, qu. 35), an intense love seeks to remove
everything that opposes it.
But this happens in different ways according to love of concupiscence,
and love of friendship. For in love of concupiscence he who desires
something intensely, is moved against all that hinders his gaining or
quietly enjoying the object of his love. It is thus that husbands are
said to be jealous of their wives, lest association with others prove a
hindrance to their exclusive individual rights. In like manner those
who seek to excel, are moved against those who seem to excel, as though
these were a hindrance to their excelling. And this is the zeal of
envy, of which it is written (Ps. 36:1): "Be not emulous of evil doers,
nor envy [zelaveris] them that work iniquity. "
On the other hand, love of friendship seeks the friend's good:
wherefore, when it is intense, it causes a man to be moved against
everything that opposes the friend's good. In this respect, a man is
said to be zealous on behalf of his friend, when he makes a point of
repelling whatever may be said or done against the friend's good. In
this way, too, a man is said to be zealous on God's behalf, when he
endeavors, to the best of his means, to repel whatever is contrary to
the honor or will of God; according to 3 Kings 19:14: "With zeal I have
been zealous for the Lord of hosts. " Again on the words of Jn. 2:17:
"The zeal of Thy house hath eaten me up," a gloss says that "a man is
eaten up with a good zeal, who strives to remedy whatever evil he
perceives; and if he cannot, bears with it and laments it. "
Reply to Objection 1: The Apostle is speaking in this passage of the
zeal of envy; which is indeed the cause of contention, not against the
object of love, but for it, and against that which is opposed to it.
Reply to Objection 2: Good is loved inasmuch as it can be communicated
to the lover. Consequently whatever hinders the perfection of this
communication, becomes hateful. Thus zeal arises from love of good. But
through defect of goodness, it happens that certain small goods cannot,
in their entirety, be possessed by many at the same time: and from the
love of such things arises the zeal of envy. But it does not arise,
properly speaking, in the case of those things which, in their
entirety, can be possessed by many: for no one envies another the
knowledge of truth, which can be known entirely by many; except perhaps
one may envy another his superiority in the knowledge of it.
Reply to Objection 3: The very fact that a man hates whatever is
opposed to the object of his love, is the effect of love. Hence zeal is
set down as an effect of love rather than of hatred.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether love is a passion that wounds the lover?
Objection 1: It would seem that love wounds the lover. For languor
denotes a hurt in the one that languishes. But love causes languor: for
it is written (Cant 2:5): "Stay me up with flowers, compass me about
with apples; because I languish with love. " Therefore love is a
wounding passion.
Objection 2: Further, melting is a kind of dissolution. But love melts
that in which it is: for it is written (Cant 5:6): "My soul melted when
my beloved spoke. " Therefore love is a dissolvent: therefore it is a
corruptive and a wounding passion.
Objection 3: Further, fervor denotes a certain excess of heat; which
excess has a corruptive effect. But love causes fervor: for Dionysius
(Coel. Hier. vii) in reckoning the properties belonging to the
Seraphim's love, includes "hot" and "piercing" and "most fervent. "
Moreover it is said of love (Cant 8:6) that "its lamps are fire and
flames. " Therefore love is a wounding and corruptive passion.
On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that "everything loves
itself with a love that holds it together," i. e. that preserves it.
Therefore love is not a wounding passion, but rather one that preserves
and perfects.
I answer that, As stated above ([1239]Q[26], AA[1],2;[1240] Q[27],
A[1]), love denotes a certain adapting of the appetitive power to some
good. Now nothing is hurt by being adapted to that which is suitable to
it; rather, if possible, it is perfected and bettered. But if a thing
be adapted to that which is not suitable to it, it is hurt and made
worse thereby. Consequently love of a suitable good perfects and
betters the lover; but love of a good which is unsuitable to the lover,
wounds and worsens him. Wherefore man is perfected and bettered chiefly
by the love of God: but is wounded and worsened by the love of sin,
according to Osee 9:10: "They became abominable, as those things which
they loved. "
And let this be understood as applying to love in respect of its formal
element, i. e. in regard to the appetite. But in respect of the material
element in the passion of love, i. e. a certain bodily change, it
happens that love is hurtful, by reason of this change being excessive:
just as it happens in the senses, and in every act of a power of the
soul that is exercised through the change of some bodily organ.
In reply to the objections, it is to be observed that four proximate
effects may be ascribed to love: viz. melting, enjoyment, languor, and
fervor. Of these the first is "melting," which is opposed to freezing.
For things that are frozen, are closely bound together, so as to be
hard to pierce. But it belongs to love that the appetite is fitted to
receive the good which is loved, inasmuch as the object loved is in the
lover, as stated above [1241](A[2]). Consequently the freezing or
hardening of the heart is a disposition incompatible with love: while
melting denotes a softening of the heart, whereby the heart shows
itself to be ready for the entrance of the beloved. If, then, the
beloved is present and possessed, pleasure or enjoyment ensues. But if
the beloved be absent, two passions arise; viz. sadness at its absence,
which is denoted by "languor" (hence Cicero in De Tusc. Quaest. iii, 11
applies the term "ailment" chiefly to sadness); and an intense desire
to possess the beloved, which is signified by "fervor. " And these are
the effects of love considered formally, according to the relation of
the appetitive power to its object. But in the passion of love, other
effects ensue, proportionate to the above, in respect of a change in
the organ.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether love is cause of all that the lover does?
Objection 1: It would seem that the lover does not do everything from
love. For love is a passion, as stated above ([1242]Q[26], A[2]). But
man does not do everything from passion: but some things he does from
choice, and some things from ignorance, as stated in Ethic. v, 8.
Therefore not everything that a man does, is done from love.
Objection 2: Further, the appetite is a principle of movement and
action in all animals, as stated in De Anima iii, 10. If, therefore,
whatever a man does is done from love, the other passions of the
appetitive faculty are superfluous.
Objection 3: Further, nothing is produced at one and the same time by
contrary causes. But some things are done from hatred. Therefore all
things are not done from love.
On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that "all things,
whatever they do, they do for the love of good. "
I answer that, Every agent acts for an end, as stated above
([1243]Q[1], A[2] ). Now the end is the good desired and loved by each
one. Wherefore it is evident that every agent, whatever it be, does
every action from love of some kind.
Reply to Objection 1: This objection takes love as a passion existing
in the sensitive appetite. But here we are speaking of love in a
general sense, inasmuch as it includes intellectual, rational, animal,
and natural love: for it is in this sense that Dionysius speaks of love
in chapter iv of De Divinis Nominibus.
Reply to Objection 2: As stated above [1244](A[5]; Q[27], A[4]) desire,
sadness and pleasure, and consequently all the other passions of the
soul, result from love. Wherefore every act proceeds from any passion,
proceeds also from love as from a first cause: and so the other
passions, which are proximate causes, are not superfluous.
Reply to Objection 3: Hatred also is a result of love, as we shall
state further on ([1245]Q[29], A[2]).
__________________________________________________________________
OF HATRED (SIX ARTICLES)
We must now consider hatred: concerning which there are six points of
inquiry:
(1) Whether evil is the cause and the object of hatred?
(2) Whether love is the cause of hatred?
(3) Whether hatred is stronger than love?
(4) Whether a man can hate himself?
(5) Whether a man can hate the truth?
(6) Whether a thing can be the object of universal hatred?
__________________________________________________________________
Whether evil is the cause and object of hatred?
Objection 1: It would seem that evil is not the object and cause of
hatred. For everything that exists, as such, is good. If therefore evil
be the object of hatred, it follows that nothing but the lack of
something can be the object of hatred: which is clearly untrue.
Objection 2: Further, hatred of evil is praise-worthy; hence (2 Macc
3:1) some are praised for that "the laws were very well kept, because
of the godliness of Onias the high-priest, and the hatred of their
souls [Douay: 'his soul'] had no evil. " If, therefore, nothing but evil
be the object of hatred, it would follow that all hatred is
commendable: and this is clearly false.
Objection 3: Further, the same thing is not at the same time both good
and evil. But the same thing is lovable and hateful to different
subjects. Therefore hatred is not only of evil, but also of good.
On the contrary, Hatred is the opposite of love. But the object of love
is good, as stated above ([1246]Q[26], A[1];[1247] Q[27], A[1]).
Therefore the object of hatred is evil.
I answer that, Since the natural appetite is the result of apprehension
(though this apprehension is not in the same subject as the natural
appetite), it seems that what applies to the inclination of the natural
appetite, applies also to the animal appetite, which does result from
an apprehension in the same subject, as stated above ([1248]Q[26],
A[1]). Now, with regard to the natural appetite, it is evident, that
just as each thing is naturally attuned and adapted to that which is
suitable to it, wherein consists natural love; so has it a natural
dissonance from that which opposes and destroys it; and this is natural
hatred. So, therefore, in the animal appetite, or in the intellectual
appetite, love is a certain harmony of the appetite with that which is
apprehended as suitable; while hatred is dissonance of the appetite
from that which is apprehended as repugnant and hurtful. Now, just as
whatever is suitable, as such, bears the aspect of good; so whatever is
repugnant, as such, bears the aspect of evil. And therefore, just as
good is the object of love, so evil is the object of hatred.
Reply to Objection 1: Being, as such, has not the aspect of repugnance
but only of fittingness; because being is common to all things. But
being, inasmuch as it is this determinate being, has an aspect of
repugnance to some determinate being. And in this way, one being is
hateful to another, and is evil; though not in itself, but by
comparison with something else.
Reply to Objection 2: Just as a thing may be apprehended as good, when
it is not truly good; so a thing may be apprehended as evil, whereas it
is not truly evil. Hence it happens sometimes that neither hatred of
evil nor love of good is good.
Reply to Objection 3: To different things the same thing may be lovable
or hateful: in respect of the natural appetite, owing to one and the
same thing being naturally suitable to one thing, and naturally
unsuitable to another: thus heat is becoming to fire and unbecoming to
water: and in respect of the animal appetite, owing to one and the same
thing being apprehended by one as good, by another as bad.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether love is a cause of hatred?
Objection 1: It would seem that love is not a cause of hatred. For "the
opposite members of a division are naturally simultaneous" (Praedic.
x). But love and hatred are opposite members of a division, since they
are contrary to one another. Therefore they are naturally simultaneous.
Therefore love is not the cause of hatred.
Objection 2: Further, of two contraries, one is not the cause of the
other. But love and hatred are contraries. Therefore love is not the
cause of hatred.
Objection 3: Further, that which follows is not the cause of that which
precedes. But hatred precedes love, seemingly: since hatred implies a
turning away from evil, whereas love implies a turning towards good.
Therefore love is not the cause of hatred.
On the contrary, Augustine says (De Civ. Dei xiv, 7,9) that all
emotions are caused by love. Therefore hatred also, since it is an
emotion of the soul, is caused by love.
I answer that, As stated above [1249](A[1]), love consists in a certain
agreement of the lover with the object loved, while hatred consists in
a certain disagreement or dissonance. Now we should consider in each
thing, what agrees with it, before that which disagrees: since a thing
disagrees with another, through destroying or hindering that which
agrees with it. Consequently love must needs precede hatred; and
nothing is hated, save through being contrary to a suitable thing which
is loved. And hence it is that every hatred is caused by love.
Reply to Objection 1: The opposite members of a division are sometimes
naturally simultaneous, both really and logically; e. g. two species of
animal, or two species of color. Sometimes they are simultaneous
logically, while, in reality, one precedes, and causes the other; e. g.
the species of numbers, figures and movements. Sometimes they are not
simultaneous either really or logically; e. g. substance and accident;
for substance is in reality the cause of accident; and being is
predicated of substance before it is predicated of accident, by a
priority of reason, because it is not predicated of accident except
inasmuch as the latter is in substance. Now love and hatred are
naturally simultaneous, logically but not really.
