ek is Senior Researcher at the
Department
of Philosophy, University of Ljubljana, Slovenia.
Hegel - Zizek - With Hegel Beyond He
?
ON JAMESON'S THE HEGEL VARIATIONS 307
? ? ? forms, spatial and temporal (from outside reality as our own histori- cal past is independent of us). The first critical point to be made here is that the features Jameson attributes to Understanding ("common-sense empirical thinking of externality, formed in the experience of solid objects and obedient to the law of non-contradiction") clearly are his- torically limited: they designate the modern/secular empiricist com- mon sense very different from, say, a primitive holistic notion of reality permeated by spiritual forces.
However, a much more impor- tant critical point concerns the way Jameson formulates the dichotomy between Understanding and Rea- son: Understanding is understood as the elementary form of analyzing, of drawing the lines of fixed dif- ferences and identities; that is, of reducing the wealth of reality to an abstract set of features. This sponta- neous tendency toward identitarian reification has to be then corrected by dialectical Reason, which faith- fully reproduces the dynamic complexity of reality by way of outlining the fluid network of rela- tions within which every identity is located. This network generates each identity and, simultaneously, causes its ultimate downfall. . . . This, however, is emphatically not the way Hegel conceives the dif- ference between Understanding and Reason--let us read carefully a well-known passage from the fore- word to Phenomenology:
To break up an idea into its ultimate elements means re- turning upon its moments, which at least do not have the form of the given idea when found, but are the im- mediate property of the self. Doubtless this analysis only arrives at thoughts which are themselves familiar elements, fixed inert determinations. But what is thus separated, and in a sense is unreal, is itself an essential moment; for just because the concrete fact is self-divided, and turns into unreality, it is something self-moving, self-active. The action of separating the ele- ments is the exercise of the force of Understanding, the most astonishing and great- est of all powers, or rather the absolute power. The circle, which is self-enclosed and at rest, and, qua substance, holds its own moments, is an immediate relation, the im- mediate, continuous relation of elements with their unity, and hence arouses no sense of wonderment. But that an accident as such, when out loose from its containing circumference,--that what is bound and held by some- thing else and actual only by being connected with it,-- should obtain an existence all its own, gain freedom and independence on its own
? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? 308 SLAVOJ Z? IZ? EK
? ? ? account--this is the porten- tous power of the negative; it is the energy of thought, of pure ego. Death, as we may call that unreality, is the most terrible thing, and to keep and hold fast what is dead demands the greatest force of all. 3
Understanding, precisely in its aspect of analyzing, tearing the unity of a thing or process apart, is here celebrated as "the most aston- ishing and greatest of all powers, or rather the absolute power"--as such, it is, surprisingly (for those who stick to the common view of dialectics), characterized in exactly the same terms as Spirit which is, with regard to the opposition be- tween Understanding and Rea- son, clearly on the side of Reason: "Spirit is, in its simple truth, con- sciousness, and forces its moments apart. " Everything turns on how we are to understand this iden- tity and difference between Un- derstanding and Reason: it is not that reason adds something to the separating power of Understand- ing, reestablishing (at some higher level) the organic unity of what Understanding has torn apart, supplementing analysis with syn- thesis; Reason is, in a way, not more but less than Understanding. It is--to put it in Hegel's well- known terms of the dichotomy between what one wants to say and what one actually says--what
Understanding, in its activity, really does, in contrast to what it wants/ means to do. Reason is therefore not another facility supplementing Understanding's one-sidedness: the very idea that there is something (the core of the substantial content of the analyzed thing) that eludes Understanding, a transrational Be- yond out of its reach, is the funda- mental illusion of Understanding. In other words, all we have to do to get from Understanding to Reason is to subtract from Understanding its constitutive illusion--Under- standing is not too abstract/violent; it is, on the contrary, as Hegel put it a propos Kant, too soft toward things, afraid to locate its violent movement of tearing things apart into things themselves. 4 In a way, it is epistemology versus ontology: the illusion of Understanding is that its own analytic power--the power to make "an accident as such, when out loose from its containing cir- cumference,--that what is bound and held by something else and ac- tual only by being connected with it,--. . . obtain an existence all its own, gain freedom and indepen- dence on its own account"--is only an abstraction, something external to true reality that persists out there intact in its inaccessible fullness. In other words, it is the standard critical view of Understanding and its power of abstraction (that it is just an impotent intellectual exercise missing the wealth of real- ity) that contains the core illusion
? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ON JAMESON'S THE HEGEL VARIATIONS 309
? ? ? of Understanding. To put it in yet another way, the mistake of Un- derstanding is to perceive its own negative activity (of separating, tearing things apart) only in its negative aspect, ignoring its posi- tive (productive) aspect--Reason is Understanding itself in its produc- tive aspect. 5
IV
Even Jameson succumbs to this classical anti-Hegelian topic when he identifies narcissism as that which "may sometimes be felt to be repulsive in the Hegelian system as such" (130) or, in short, as the cen- tral weakness of Hegel's thought expressed in his claim that rea- son should find itself in the actual world:
We thereby search the whole world, and outer space, and end up only touching our- selves, only seeing our own face persist through multitu- dinous differences and forms of otherness. Never truly to encounter the not-I, to come face to face with radical oth- erness (or, even worse, to find ourselves in an historical dy- namic in which it is precisely difference and otherness which is relentlessly being stamped out): such is the di- lemma of the Hegelian dia- lectic, which contemporary
philosophies of difference and otherness seem only able to confront with mystical evocations and imperatives. (131)
Instead of trying to under- mine or overcome this narcissism from the outside, emphasizing the preponderance of the objec- tive (or that the Whole is the non- true and all other similar motifs of Theodore Adorno's rejection of identitarian idealism), one should rather problematize the figure of Hegel criticized here by way of asking a simple question: which Hegel is our point of reference here? Do not Georg Luka? cs and Adorno both refer to the idealist- subjectivist (mis)reading of Hegel, to the standard image of Hegel as the absolute idealist who asserted Spirit as the true agent of history, its Subject-Substance? Within this framework, capital can effectively appear as a new embodiment of the Hegelian Spirit, an abstract mon- ster that moves and mediates itself, parasitizing upon the activity of actually existing individuals. This is why Luka? cs also remains all too idealist when he proposes to simply replace the Hegelian Spirit with the proletariat as the Subject-Object of History: Luka? cs here is not re- ally Hegelian, but a pre-Hegelian idealist.
If, however, one problema- tizes this presupposition shared by Luka? cs and Adorno, another
? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? 310 SLAVOJ Z? IZ? EK
? ? ? Hegel appears, a more materialist Hegel for whom reconciliation be- tween Subject and Substance does not mean that the subject swal- lows its substance, internalizing it into its own subordinate moment. Reconciliation rather amounts to a much more modest overlapping or redoubling of the two separations: the subject has to recognize in its alienation from the Substance the separation of the Substance from itself. This overlapping is what is missed in the Feuerbach-Marxian logic of de-alienation in which the subject overcomes its alienation by recognizing itself as the active agent who itself posited what appears to it as its substantial presupposition. In the Hegelian reconciliation be- tween Subject and Substance, there is no absolute Subject that, in total self-transparency, appropriates or internalizes all objective substantial content. But "reconciliation" also doesn't mean (as it does in the line of German idealism from Ho? lderlin to Schelling) that the subject should renounce its hubris of perceiving itself as the axis of the world and accept its constitutive decentering, its dependency on some primordial abyssal Absolute that is beyond/ beneath the subject/object divide and, as such, also beyond subjective conceptual grasp. The subject is not its own origin: Hegel firmly rejects Fichte's notion of the absolute I that posits itself and is nothing but the pure activity of this self-positing. But the subject is also not just a
secondary accidental appendix/ outgrowth of some presubjective substantial reality: there is no sub- stantial Being to which the subject can return, no encompassing or- ganic Order of Being in which the subject has to find its proper place. Reconciliation between subject and substance means the acceptance of this radical lack of any firm foun- dational point: the subject is not its own origin, it comes second, it is dependent upon its substantial pre- suppositions; but these presupposi- tions also do not have a substantial consistency of their own but are al- ways retroactively posited.
What this also means is that Communism should no longer be conceived as the subjective (re)ap- propriation of the alienated sub- stantial content--all versions of reconciliation as "subject swallows the substance" should be rejected. So, again, reconciliation is the full acceptance of the abyss of the de- substantialized process as the only actuality there is: the subject has no substantial actuality, it comes sec- ond, it only emerges through the process of separation, of overcom- ing of its presuppositions, and these presuppositions are also just a ret- roactive effect of the same process of their overcoming. The result is thus that there is, at both extremes of the process, a failure/negativity inscribed into the very heart of the entity we are dealing with. If the status of the subject is thoroughly processual, then it emerges through
? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ON JAMESON'S THE HEGEL VARIATIONS 311
? ? ? the very failure to fully actualize it- self. This brings us again to one of the possible formal definitions of subject: a subject tries to articulate (express) itself in a signifying chain, this articulation fails, and by means and through this failure, the subject emerges; the subject is the failure of its signifying representation--this is why Lacan writes the subject of the signifier as ", as "barred. " In a love letter, the very failure of the writer to formulate his declaration clearly and efficiently, his oscilla- tions, the letter's fragmentation, etc. , can in themselves be the proof (perhaps the necessary and the only reliable proof) that the professed love is authentic--here, the very failure to deliver the message prop- erly is the sign of its authenticity. If the message is delivered smoothly, it arouses suspicions that it is part of a well-planned approach, or that the writer loves himself, the beauty of his writing, more than his love object; that is, that the object is ef- fectively reduced to a pretext for engaging in the narcissistically sat- isfying activity of writing.
And the same goes for sub- stance: substance is not only al- ways already lost but comes to be only through its loss, as a second- ary return-to-itself--which means that substance is always already subjectivized. In reconciliation be- tween subject and substance, both poles thus lose their firm iden- tity. Let us take the case of ecol- ogy: radical emancipatory politics
should aim neither at the complete mastery over nature nor at the hu- manity's humble acceptance of the predominance of Mother Earth. Rather, nature should be exposed in all its catastrophic contingency and indeterminacy, and human agency assumed in the whole un- predictability of its consequences-- viewed from this perspective of the "other Hegel," the revolutionary act no longer involves as its agent the Luka? csian substance-subject, the agent who knows what it does while doing it.
Apropos Hegel's reconciliation in a modern postrevolutionary state, Jameson proposes the out- lines of a higher-enlarged version of the Hegelian reconciliation, a version appropriate for our global capitalist epoch: the project of a human age characterized by pro- duction-for-us (the end of classes) and ecology (113-15). Jameson's view is that, far from standing for the ultimate end of history, the rec- onciliation proposed at the end of the chapter on Spirit in Phenome- nology is a temporary fragile synthe- sis--Hegel himself was aware that this reconciliation is threatened, as is clear from his panicky reaction to the revolution of 1830 and the first signs of universal democracy. (Re- call his furious rejection of the Brit- ish electoral Reform Bill, the first step toward universal elections. ) Is it then not consequent that, in view of the new contradictions of the nineteenth-century capitalist
? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? 312 SLAVOJ Z? IZ? EK
? ? ? system that exploded the frag- ile Hegelian synthesis, a renewed Hegelian approach that remains faithful to the idea of concrete uni- versality, of universal rights for all, "calls in its very structure for the subsequent enlargements of later history" (115) and for a new project of reconciliation? Such a move is nonetheless illegitimate: it doesn't take into account radically enough that the same paradox as that of the retroactive positing of presup- positions holds also for the future. Let us take the case of a nation: to paraphrase an old critic of Ernest Renan, a nation is a group of people united by a mistaken view about the past, a hatred of their present neighbors, and dangerous illusions about their future. (Say, today's Slo- venes are united by the myths about a Slovene kingdom in the eighth century, their hatred of [at this mo- ment] Croats, and the illusion that the Slovenes are on their way to become the next Switzerland. ) Each historical form is a totality that en- compasses not only its retroactively posited past but also its own future, a future that is by definition never realized: it is the immanent future of this present, so that, when the present form disintegrates, it under- mines also its past and its future.
This is why Hegel was right to insist that the owl of Minerva takes off only at dusk; and this is why the standard Communist project was utopian precisely insofar as it was
not radical enough; that is, insofar as, in it, the fundamental capital- ist thrust of unleashed productivity survived, deprived of its concrete contradictory conditions of exis- tence. The insufficiency of Hei- degger, Adorno, and Horkheimer, etc. , resides in their abandonment of the concrete social analysis of capitalism: in their very critique or overcoming of Marx, they in a way repeat Marx's mistake--like Marx, they perceive the unleashed pro- ductivity as something ultimately independent of the concrete capital- ist social formation. Capitalism and Communism are not two different historical realizations, two species, of instrumental reason--instru- mental reason as such is capitalist, grounded in capitalist relations, and "really existing Socialism" failed be- cause it was ultimately a subspecies of capitalism, an ideological attempt to have a cake and eat it, to break from capitalism while retaining its key ingredient. In other words. Marx's notion of the Communist society is itself the inherent capital- ist fantasy; that is, a phantasmatic scenario for resolving the capitalist antagonism he so aptly described. In other words, our wager is that, even if we remove the teleological notion of Communism (the society of the fully unleashed productivity) as the implicit standard by which Marx, as it were, measures the alienation of the existing society, the bulk of his critique of political economy, the
? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ON JAMESON'S THE HEGEL VARIATIONS 313
? ? ? insight into the self-propelling vi- cious cycle of capitalist (re)produc- tion, survives.
The task of today's thought is thus double: on the one hand, how to repeat the Marxist critique of political economy without the uto- pian/ideological notion of Com- munism as its inherent standard; on the other hand, how to imagine ef- fectively breaking out of the capital- ist horizon without falling into the trap of returning to the eminently premodern notion of a balanced, (self-)restrained society (the pre- Cartesian temptation to which most of today's ecology succumbs).
Slavoj Z? iz?
ek is Senior Researcher at the Department of Philosophy, University of Ljubljana, Slovenia. His latest publica- tions are Living in the End Times (Verso, 2010) and First as Tragedy, Then as Farce (Verso, 2010).
NOTES
1. G. K. Chesterton, "The Slavery of the Mind" (1929), www. basilica. org/pages/
ebooks/G. K. Chesterton-The Thing. pdf (accessed 8 July 2011).
2. G. K. Chesterton, The Everlasting Man (1926), www. worldinvisible. com/ library/chesterton/everlasting/content. htm (accessed 8 July 2011).
3. G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), 18-19.
4. There is a wonderfully vulgar Jewish joke about a Polish-Jewish wife, tired after a hard day's work, when her hus- band comes home, also tired but horny, telling her, "I cannot make love to you now, but I need a release--can you suck me and swallow my sperm, this would help me a lot! " The wife replies, "I am too tired to do that now, darling--why don't you just masturbate and finish in a glass, and I will drink it in the morn- ing! " Does not this wife--contrary to the cliche? about the holistic-intuitive reasoning of women as opposed to the masculine rational analysis--provide an example of the ruthless feminine use of Understanding, of its power to separate what naturally belongs together?
5. In a strict homology to this Hegelian logic, it is meaningless to demand that psychoanalysis be supplemented by psychosynthesis, reestablishing the organic unity of the person shattered by psychoanalysis: psychoanalysis already is this synthesis.
Copyright of Criticism is the property of Wayne State University Press and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.
? ? ? forms, spatial and temporal (from outside reality as our own histori- cal past is independent of us). The first critical point to be made here is that the features Jameson attributes to Understanding ("common-sense empirical thinking of externality, formed in the experience of solid objects and obedient to the law of non-contradiction") clearly are his- torically limited: they designate the modern/secular empiricist com- mon sense very different from, say, a primitive holistic notion of reality permeated by spiritual forces.
However, a much more impor- tant critical point concerns the way Jameson formulates the dichotomy between Understanding and Rea- son: Understanding is understood as the elementary form of analyzing, of drawing the lines of fixed dif- ferences and identities; that is, of reducing the wealth of reality to an abstract set of features. This sponta- neous tendency toward identitarian reification has to be then corrected by dialectical Reason, which faith- fully reproduces the dynamic complexity of reality by way of outlining the fluid network of rela- tions within which every identity is located. This network generates each identity and, simultaneously, causes its ultimate downfall. . . . This, however, is emphatically not the way Hegel conceives the dif- ference between Understanding and Reason--let us read carefully a well-known passage from the fore- word to Phenomenology:
To break up an idea into its ultimate elements means re- turning upon its moments, which at least do not have the form of the given idea when found, but are the im- mediate property of the self. Doubtless this analysis only arrives at thoughts which are themselves familiar elements, fixed inert determinations. But what is thus separated, and in a sense is unreal, is itself an essential moment; for just because the concrete fact is self-divided, and turns into unreality, it is something self-moving, self-active. The action of separating the ele- ments is the exercise of the force of Understanding, the most astonishing and great- est of all powers, or rather the absolute power. The circle, which is self-enclosed and at rest, and, qua substance, holds its own moments, is an immediate relation, the im- mediate, continuous relation of elements with their unity, and hence arouses no sense of wonderment. But that an accident as such, when out loose from its containing circumference,--that what is bound and held by some- thing else and actual only by being connected with it,-- should obtain an existence all its own, gain freedom and independence on its own
? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? 308 SLAVOJ Z? IZ? EK
? ? ? account--this is the porten- tous power of the negative; it is the energy of thought, of pure ego. Death, as we may call that unreality, is the most terrible thing, and to keep and hold fast what is dead demands the greatest force of all. 3
Understanding, precisely in its aspect of analyzing, tearing the unity of a thing or process apart, is here celebrated as "the most aston- ishing and greatest of all powers, or rather the absolute power"--as such, it is, surprisingly (for those who stick to the common view of dialectics), characterized in exactly the same terms as Spirit which is, with regard to the opposition be- tween Understanding and Rea- son, clearly on the side of Reason: "Spirit is, in its simple truth, con- sciousness, and forces its moments apart. " Everything turns on how we are to understand this iden- tity and difference between Un- derstanding and Reason: it is not that reason adds something to the separating power of Understand- ing, reestablishing (at some higher level) the organic unity of what Understanding has torn apart, supplementing analysis with syn- thesis; Reason is, in a way, not more but less than Understanding. It is--to put it in Hegel's well- known terms of the dichotomy between what one wants to say and what one actually says--what
Understanding, in its activity, really does, in contrast to what it wants/ means to do. Reason is therefore not another facility supplementing Understanding's one-sidedness: the very idea that there is something (the core of the substantial content of the analyzed thing) that eludes Understanding, a transrational Be- yond out of its reach, is the funda- mental illusion of Understanding. In other words, all we have to do to get from Understanding to Reason is to subtract from Understanding its constitutive illusion--Under- standing is not too abstract/violent; it is, on the contrary, as Hegel put it a propos Kant, too soft toward things, afraid to locate its violent movement of tearing things apart into things themselves. 4 In a way, it is epistemology versus ontology: the illusion of Understanding is that its own analytic power--the power to make "an accident as such, when out loose from its containing cir- cumference,--that what is bound and held by something else and ac- tual only by being connected with it,--. . . obtain an existence all its own, gain freedom and indepen- dence on its own account"--is only an abstraction, something external to true reality that persists out there intact in its inaccessible fullness. In other words, it is the standard critical view of Understanding and its power of abstraction (that it is just an impotent intellectual exercise missing the wealth of real- ity) that contains the core illusion
? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ON JAMESON'S THE HEGEL VARIATIONS 309
? ? ? of Understanding. To put it in yet another way, the mistake of Un- derstanding is to perceive its own negative activity (of separating, tearing things apart) only in its negative aspect, ignoring its posi- tive (productive) aspect--Reason is Understanding itself in its produc- tive aspect. 5
IV
Even Jameson succumbs to this classical anti-Hegelian topic when he identifies narcissism as that which "may sometimes be felt to be repulsive in the Hegelian system as such" (130) or, in short, as the cen- tral weakness of Hegel's thought expressed in his claim that rea- son should find itself in the actual world:
We thereby search the whole world, and outer space, and end up only touching our- selves, only seeing our own face persist through multitu- dinous differences and forms of otherness. Never truly to encounter the not-I, to come face to face with radical oth- erness (or, even worse, to find ourselves in an historical dy- namic in which it is precisely difference and otherness which is relentlessly being stamped out): such is the di- lemma of the Hegelian dia- lectic, which contemporary
philosophies of difference and otherness seem only able to confront with mystical evocations and imperatives. (131)
Instead of trying to under- mine or overcome this narcissism from the outside, emphasizing the preponderance of the objec- tive (or that the Whole is the non- true and all other similar motifs of Theodore Adorno's rejection of identitarian idealism), one should rather problematize the figure of Hegel criticized here by way of asking a simple question: which Hegel is our point of reference here? Do not Georg Luka? cs and Adorno both refer to the idealist- subjectivist (mis)reading of Hegel, to the standard image of Hegel as the absolute idealist who asserted Spirit as the true agent of history, its Subject-Substance? Within this framework, capital can effectively appear as a new embodiment of the Hegelian Spirit, an abstract mon- ster that moves and mediates itself, parasitizing upon the activity of actually existing individuals. This is why Luka? cs also remains all too idealist when he proposes to simply replace the Hegelian Spirit with the proletariat as the Subject-Object of History: Luka? cs here is not re- ally Hegelian, but a pre-Hegelian idealist.
If, however, one problema- tizes this presupposition shared by Luka? cs and Adorno, another
? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? 310 SLAVOJ Z? IZ? EK
? ? ? Hegel appears, a more materialist Hegel for whom reconciliation be- tween Subject and Substance does not mean that the subject swal- lows its substance, internalizing it into its own subordinate moment. Reconciliation rather amounts to a much more modest overlapping or redoubling of the two separations: the subject has to recognize in its alienation from the Substance the separation of the Substance from itself. This overlapping is what is missed in the Feuerbach-Marxian logic of de-alienation in which the subject overcomes its alienation by recognizing itself as the active agent who itself posited what appears to it as its substantial presupposition. In the Hegelian reconciliation be- tween Subject and Substance, there is no absolute Subject that, in total self-transparency, appropriates or internalizes all objective substantial content. But "reconciliation" also doesn't mean (as it does in the line of German idealism from Ho? lderlin to Schelling) that the subject should renounce its hubris of perceiving itself as the axis of the world and accept its constitutive decentering, its dependency on some primordial abyssal Absolute that is beyond/ beneath the subject/object divide and, as such, also beyond subjective conceptual grasp. The subject is not its own origin: Hegel firmly rejects Fichte's notion of the absolute I that posits itself and is nothing but the pure activity of this self-positing. But the subject is also not just a
secondary accidental appendix/ outgrowth of some presubjective substantial reality: there is no sub- stantial Being to which the subject can return, no encompassing or- ganic Order of Being in which the subject has to find its proper place. Reconciliation between subject and substance means the acceptance of this radical lack of any firm foun- dational point: the subject is not its own origin, it comes second, it is dependent upon its substantial pre- suppositions; but these presupposi- tions also do not have a substantial consistency of their own but are al- ways retroactively posited.
What this also means is that Communism should no longer be conceived as the subjective (re)ap- propriation of the alienated sub- stantial content--all versions of reconciliation as "subject swallows the substance" should be rejected. So, again, reconciliation is the full acceptance of the abyss of the de- substantialized process as the only actuality there is: the subject has no substantial actuality, it comes sec- ond, it only emerges through the process of separation, of overcom- ing of its presuppositions, and these presuppositions are also just a ret- roactive effect of the same process of their overcoming. The result is thus that there is, at both extremes of the process, a failure/negativity inscribed into the very heart of the entity we are dealing with. If the status of the subject is thoroughly processual, then it emerges through
? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ON JAMESON'S THE HEGEL VARIATIONS 311
? ? ? the very failure to fully actualize it- self. This brings us again to one of the possible formal definitions of subject: a subject tries to articulate (express) itself in a signifying chain, this articulation fails, and by means and through this failure, the subject emerges; the subject is the failure of its signifying representation--this is why Lacan writes the subject of the signifier as ", as "barred. " In a love letter, the very failure of the writer to formulate his declaration clearly and efficiently, his oscilla- tions, the letter's fragmentation, etc. , can in themselves be the proof (perhaps the necessary and the only reliable proof) that the professed love is authentic--here, the very failure to deliver the message prop- erly is the sign of its authenticity. If the message is delivered smoothly, it arouses suspicions that it is part of a well-planned approach, or that the writer loves himself, the beauty of his writing, more than his love object; that is, that the object is ef- fectively reduced to a pretext for engaging in the narcissistically sat- isfying activity of writing.
And the same goes for sub- stance: substance is not only al- ways already lost but comes to be only through its loss, as a second- ary return-to-itself--which means that substance is always already subjectivized. In reconciliation be- tween subject and substance, both poles thus lose their firm iden- tity. Let us take the case of ecol- ogy: radical emancipatory politics
should aim neither at the complete mastery over nature nor at the hu- manity's humble acceptance of the predominance of Mother Earth. Rather, nature should be exposed in all its catastrophic contingency and indeterminacy, and human agency assumed in the whole un- predictability of its consequences-- viewed from this perspective of the "other Hegel," the revolutionary act no longer involves as its agent the Luka? csian substance-subject, the agent who knows what it does while doing it.
Apropos Hegel's reconciliation in a modern postrevolutionary state, Jameson proposes the out- lines of a higher-enlarged version of the Hegelian reconciliation, a version appropriate for our global capitalist epoch: the project of a human age characterized by pro- duction-for-us (the end of classes) and ecology (113-15). Jameson's view is that, far from standing for the ultimate end of history, the rec- onciliation proposed at the end of the chapter on Spirit in Phenome- nology is a temporary fragile synthe- sis--Hegel himself was aware that this reconciliation is threatened, as is clear from his panicky reaction to the revolution of 1830 and the first signs of universal democracy. (Re- call his furious rejection of the Brit- ish electoral Reform Bill, the first step toward universal elections. ) Is it then not consequent that, in view of the new contradictions of the nineteenth-century capitalist
? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? 312 SLAVOJ Z? IZ? EK
? ? ? system that exploded the frag- ile Hegelian synthesis, a renewed Hegelian approach that remains faithful to the idea of concrete uni- versality, of universal rights for all, "calls in its very structure for the subsequent enlargements of later history" (115) and for a new project of reconciliation? Such a move is nonetheless illegitimate: it doesn't take into account radically enough that the same paradox as that of the retroactive positing of presup- positions holds also for the future. Let us take the case of a nation: to paraphrase an old critic of Ernest Renan, a nation is a group of people united by a mistaken view about the past, a hatred of their present neighbors, and dangerous illusions about their future. (Say, today's Slo- venes are united by the myths about a Slovene kingdom in the eighth century, their hatred of [at this mo- ment] Croats, and the illusion that the Slovenes are on their way to become the next Switzerland. ) Each historical form is a totality that en- compasses not only its retroactively posited past but also its own future, a future that is by definition never realized: it is the immanent future of this present, so that, when the present form disintegrates, it under- mines also its past and its future.
This is why Hegel was right to insist that the owl of Minerva takes off only at dusk; and this is why the standard Communist project was utopian precisely insofar as it was
not radical enough; that is, insofar as, in it, the fundamental capital- ist thrust of unleashed productivity survived, deprived of its concrete contradictory conditions of exis- tence. The insufficiency of Hei- degger, Adorno, and Horkheimer, etc. , resides in their abandonment of the concrete social analysis of capitalism: in their very critique or overcoming of Marx, they in a way repeat Marx's mistake--like Marx, they perceive the unleashed pro- ductivity as something ultimately independent of the concrete capital- ist social formation. Capitalism and Communism are not two different historical realizations, two species, of instrumental reason--instru- mental reason as such is capitalist, grounded in capitalist relations, and "really existing Socialism" failed be- cause it was ultimately a subspecies of capitalism, an ideological attempt to have a cake and eat it, to break from capitalism while retaining its key ingredient. In other words. Marx's notion of the Communist society is itself the inherent capital- ist fantasy; that is, a phantasmatic scenario for resolving the capitalist antagonism he so aptly described. In other words, our wager is that, even if we remove the teleological notion of Communism (the society of the fully unleashed productivity) as the implicit standard by which Marx, as it were, measures the alienation of the existing society, the bulk of his critique of political economy, the
? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ON JAMESON'S THE HEGEL VARIATIONS 313
? ? ? insight into the self-propelling vi- cious cycle of capitalist (re)produc- tion, survives.
The task of today's thought is thus double: on the one hand, how to repeat the Marxist critique of political economy without the uto- pian/ideological notion of Com- munism as its inherent standard; on the other hand, how to imagine ef- fectively breaking out of the capital- ist horizon without falling into the trap of returning to the eminently premodern notion of a balanced, (self-)restrained society (the pre- Cartesian temptation to which most of today's ecology succumbs).
Slavoj Z? iz?
ek is Senior Researcher at the Department of Philosophy, University of Ljubljana, Slovenia. His latest publica- tions are Living in the End Times (Verso, 2010) and First as Tragedy, Then as Farce (Verso, 2010).
NOTES
1. G. K. Chesterton, "The Slavery of the Mind" (1929), www. basilica. org/pages/
ebooks/G. K. Chesterton-The Thing. pdf (accessed 8 July 2011).
2. G. K. Chesterton, The Everlasting Man (1926), www. worldinvisible. com/ library/chesterton/everlasting/content. htm (accessed 8 July 2011).
3. G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), 18-19.
4. There is a wonderfully vulgar Jewish joke about a Polish-Jewish wife, tired after a hard day's work, when her hus- band comes home, also tired but horny, telling her, "I cannot make love to you now, but I need a release--can you suck me and swallow my sperm, this would help me a lot! " The wife replies, "I am too tired to do that now, darling--why don't you just masturbate and finish in a glass, and I will drink it in the morn- ing! " Does not this wife--contrary to the cliche? about the holistic-intuitive reasoning of women as opposed to the masculine rational analysis--provide an example of the ruthless feminine use of Understanding, of its power to separate what naturally belongs together?
5. In a strict homology to this Hegelian logic, it is meaningless to demand that psychoanalysis be supplemented by psychosynthesis, reestablishing the organic unity of the person shattered by psychoanalysis: psychoanalysis already is this synthesis.
Copyright of Criticism is the property of Wayne State University Press and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.