Now virtues admit of greater
abundance
and
increase: for it is written (Mat.
increase: for it is written (Mat.
Summa Theologica
[1605] Q[61], A[4],
OBJ[1]). Augustine also gives the same reason (De Trin. vi, 4).
Others, however, differentiate these virtues in respect of their
matters, and it is in this way that Aristotle assigns the reason for
their connection (Ethic. vi, 13). Because, as stated above
([1606]Q[58], A[4]), no moral virtue can be without prudence; since it
is proper to moral virtue to make a right choice, for it is an elective
habit. Now right choice requires not only the inclination to a due end,
which inclination is the direct outcome of moral virtue, but also
correct choice of things conducive to the end, which choice is made by
prudence, that counsels, judges, and commands in those things that are
directed to the end. In like manner one cannot have prudence unless one
has the moral virtues: since prudence is "right reason about things to
be done," and the starting point of reason is the end of the thing to
be done, to which end man is rightly disposed by moral virtue. Hence,
just as we cannot have speculative science unless we have the
understanding of the principles, so neither can we have prudence
without the moral virtues: and from this it follows clearly that the
moral virtues are connected with one another.
Reply to Objection 1: Some moral virtues perfect man as regards his
general state, in other words, with regard to those things which have
to be done in every kind of human life. Hence man needs to exercise
himself at the same time in the matters of all moral virtues. And if he
exercise himself, by good deeds, in all such matters, he will acquire
the habits of all the moral virtues. But if he exercise himself by good
deeds in regard to one matter, but not in regard to another, for
instance, by behaving well in matters of anger, but not in matters of
concupiscence; he will indeed acquire a certain habit of restraining
his anger; but this habit will lack the nature of virtue, through the
absence of prudence, which is wanting in matters of concupiscence. In
the same way, natural inclinations fail to have the complete character
of virtue, if prudence be lacking.
But there are some moral virtues which perfect man with regard to some
eminent state, such as magnificence and magnanimity; and since it does
not happen to all in common to be exercised in the matter of such
virtues, it is possible for a man to have the other moral virtues,
without actually having the habits of these virtues---provided we speak
of acquired virtue. Nevertheless, when once a man has acquired those
other virtues he possesses these in proximate potentiality. Because
when, by practice, a man has acquired liberality in small gifts and
expenditure, if he were to come in for a large sum of money, he would
acquire the habit of magnificence with but little practice: even as a
geometrician, by dint of little study, acquires scientific knowledge
about some conclusion which had never been presented to his mind
before. Now we speak of having a thing when we are on the point of
having it, according to the saying of the Philosopher (Phys. ii, text.
56): "That which is scarcely lacking is not lacking at all. "
This suffices for the Reply to the Second Objection.
Reply to Objection 3: The intellectual virtues are about divers matters
having no relation to one another, as is clearly the case with the
various sciences and arts. Hence we do not observe in them the
connection that is to be found among the moral virtues, which are about
passions and operations, that are clearly related to one another. For
all the passions have their rise in certain initial passions, viz. love
and hatred, and terminate in certain others, viz. pleasure and sorrow.
In like manner all the operations that are the matter of moral virtue
are related to one another, and to the passions. Hence the whole matter
of moral virtues falls under the one rule of prudence.
Nevertheless, all intelligible things are related to first principles.
And in this way, all the intellectual virtues depend on the
understanding of principles; even as prudence depends on the moral
virtues, as stated. On the other hand, the universal principles which
are the object of the virtue of understanding of principles, do not
depend on the conclusions, which are the objects of the other
intellectual virtues, as do the moral virtues depend on prudence,
because the appetite, in a fashion, moves the reason, and the reason
the appetite, as stated above ([1607]Q[9], A[1];[1608] Q[58], A[5], ad
1).
Reply to Objection 4: Those things to which the moral virtues incline,
are as the principles of prudence: whereas the products of art are not
the principles, but the matter of art. Now it is evident that, though
reason may be right in one part of the matter, and not in another, yet
in no way can it be called right reason, if it be deficient in any
principle whatever. Thus, if a man be wrong about the principle, "A
whole is greater than its part," he cannot acquire the science of
geometry, because he must necessarily wander from the truth in his
conclusion. Moreover, things "done" are related to one another, but not
things "made," as stated above (ad 3). Consequently the lack of
prudence in one department of things to be done, would result in a
deficiency affecting other things to be done: whereas this does not
occur in things to be made.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether moral virtues can be without charity?
Objection 1: It would seem that moral virtues can be without charity.
For it is stated in the Liber Sentent. Prosperi vii, that "every virtue
save charity may be common to the good and bad. " But "charity can be in
none except the good," as stated in the same book. Therefore the other
virtues can be had without charity.
Objection 2: Further, moral virtues can be acquired by means of human
acts, as stated in Ethic. ii, 1,2, whereas charity cannot be had
otherwise than by infusion, according to Rom. 5:5: "The charity of God
is poured forth in our hearts by the Holy Ghost Who is given to us. "
Therefore it is possible to have the other virtues without charity.
Objection 3: Further, the moral virtues are connected together, through
depending on prudence. But charity does not depend on prudence; indeed,
it surpasses prudence, according to Eph. 3:19: "The charity of Christ,
which surpasseth all knowledge. " Therefore the moral virtues are not
connected with charity, and can be without it.
On the contrary, It is written (1 Jn. 3:14): "He that loveth not,
abideth in death. " Now the spiritual life is perfected by the virtues,
since it is "by them" that "we lead a good life," as Augustine states
(De Lib. Arb. ii, 17,19). Therefore they cannot be without the love of
charity.
I answer that, As stated above (Q[63], A[2]), it is possible by means
of human works to acquire moral virtues, in so far as they produce good
works that are directed to an end not surpassing the natural power of
man: and when they are acquired thus, they can be without charity, even
as they were in many of the Gentiles. But in so far as they produce
good works in proportion to a supernatural last end, thus they have the
character of virtue, truly and perfectly; and cannot be acquired by
human acts, but are infused by God. Such like moral virtues cannot be
without charity. For it has been stated above [1609](A[1]; Q[58],
AA[4],5) that the other moral virtues cannot be without prudence; and
that prudence cannot be without the moral virtues, because these latter
make man well disposed to certain ends, which are the starting-point of
the procedure of prudence. Now for prudence to proceed aright, it is
much more necessary that man be well disposed towards his ultimate end,
which is the effect of charity, than that he be well disposed in
respect of other ends, which is the effect of moral virtue: just as in
speculative matters right reason has greatest need of the first
indemonstrable principle, that "contradictories cannot both be true at
the same time. " It is therefore evident that neither can infused
prudence be without charity; nor, consequently, the other moral
virtues, since they cannot be without prudence.
It is therefore clear from what has been said that only the infused
virtues are perfect, and deserve to be called virtues simply: since
they direct man well to the ultimate end. But the other virtues, those,
namely, that are acquired, are virtues in a restricted sense, but not
simply: for they direct man well in respect of the last end in some
particular genus of action, but not in respect of the last end simply.
Hence a gloss of Augustine [*Cf. Lib. Sentent. Prosperi cvi. ] on the
words, "All that is not of faith is sin" (Rom. 14:23), says: "He that
fails to acknowledge the truth, has no true virtue, even if his conduct
be good. "
Reply to Objection 1: Virtue, in the words quoted, denotes imperfect
virtue. Else if we take moral virtue in its perfect state, "it makes
its possessor good," and consequently cannot be in the wicked.
Reply to Objection 2: This argument holds good of virtue in the sense
of acquired virtue.
Reply to Objection 3: Though charity surpasses science and prudence,
yet prudence depends on charity, as stated: and consequently so do all
the infused moral virtues.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether charity can be without moral virtue?
Objection 1: It would seem possible to have charity without the moral
virtues. For when one thing suffices for a certain purpose, it is
superfluous to employ others. Now charity alone suffices for the
fulfilment of all the works of virtue, as is clear from 1 Cor. 13:4,
seqq. : "Charity is patient, is kind," etc. Therefore it seems that if
one has charity, other virtues are superfluous.
Objection 2: Further, he that has a habit of virtue easily performs the
works of that virtue, and those works are pleasing to him for their own
sake: hence "pleasure taken in a work is a sign of habit" (Ethic. ii,
3). Now many have charity, being free from mortal sin, and yet they
find it difficult to do works of virtue; nor are these works pleasing
to them for their own sake, but only for the sake of charity. Therefore
many have charity without the other virtues.
Objection 3: Further, charity is to be found in every saint: and yet
there are some saints who are without certain virtues. For Bede says
(on Lk. 17:10) that the saints are more humbled on account of their not
having certain virtues, than rejoiced at the virtues they have.
Therefore, if a man has charity, it does not follow of necessity that
he has all the moral virtues.
On the contrary, The whole Law is fulfilled through charity, for it is
written (Rom. 13:8): "He that loveth his neighbor, hath fulfilled the
Law. " Now it is not possible to fulfil the whole Law, without having
all the moral virtues: since the law contains precepts about all acts
of virtue, as stated in Ethic. v, 1,2. Therefore he that has charity,
has all the moral virtues. Moreover, Augustine says in a letter (Epis.
clxvii) [*Cf. Serm. xxxix and xlvi de Temp. ] that charity contains all
the cardinal virtues.
I answer that, All the moral virtues are infused together with charity.
The reason for this is that God operates no less perfectly in works of
grace than in works of nature. Now, in the works of nature, we find
that whenever a thing contains a principle of certain works, it has
also whatever is necessary for their execution: thus animals are
provided with organs whereby to perform the actions that their souls
empower them to do. Now it is evident that charity, inasmuch as it
directs man to his last end, is the principle of all the good works
that are referable to his last end. Wherefore all the moral virtues
must needs be infused together with charity, since it is through them
that man performs each different kind of good work.
It is therefore clear that the infused moral virtues are connected, not
only through prudence, but also on account of charity: and, again, that
whoever loses charity through mortal sin, forfeits all the infused
moral virtues.
Reply to Objection 1: In order that the act of a lower power be
perfect, not only must there be perfection in the higher, but also in
the lower power: for if the principal agent were well disposed, perfect
action would not follow, if the instrument also were not well disposed.
Consequently, in order that man work well in things referred to the
end, he needs not only a virtue disposing him well to the end, but also
those virtues which dispose him well to whatever is referred to the
end: for the virtue which regards the end is the chief and moving
principle in respect of those things that are referred to the end.
Therefore it is necessary to have the moral virtues together with
charity.
Reply to Objection 2: It happens sometimes that a man who has a habit,
finds it difficult to act in accordance with the habit, and
consequently feels no pleasure and complacency in the act, on account
of some impediment supervening from without: thus a man who has a habit
of science, finds it difficult to understand, through being sleepy or
unwell. In like manner sometimes the habits of moral virtue experience
difficulty in their works, by reason of certain ordinary dispositions
remaining from previous acts. This difficulty does not occur in respect
of acquired moral virtue: because the repeated acts by which they are
acquired, remove also the contrary dispositions.
Reply to Objection 3: Certain saints are said not to have certain
virtues, in so far as they experience difficulty in the acts of those
virtues, for the reason stated; although they have the habits of all
the virtues.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether faith and hope can be without charity?
Objection 1: It would seem that faith and hope are never without
charity. Because, since they are theological virtues, they seem to be
more excellent than even the infused moral virtues. But the infused
moral virtues cannot be without charity. Neither therefore can faith
and hope be without charity.
Objection 2: Further, "no man believes unwillingly" as Augustine says
(Tract. xxvi in Joan. ). But charity is in the will as a perfection
thereof, as stated above ([1610]Q[62], A[3]). Therefore faith cannot be
without charity.
Objection 3: Further, Augustine says (Enchiridion viii) that "there can
be no hope without love. " But love is charity: for it is of this love
that he speaks. Therefore hope cannot be without charity.
On the contrary, A gloss on Mat. 1:2 says that "faith begets hope, and
hope, charity. " Now the begetter precedes the begotten, and can be
without it. Therefore faith can be without hope; and hope, without
charity.
I answer that, Faith and hope, like the moral virtues, can be
considered in two ways; first in an inchoate state; secondly, as
complete virtues. For since virtue is directed to the doing of good
works, perfect virtue is that which gives the faculty of doing a
perfectly good work, and this consists in not only doing what is good,
but also in doing it well. Else, if what is done is good, but not well
done, it will not be perfectly good; wherefore neither will the habit
that is the principle of such an act, have the perfect character of
virtue. For instance, if a man do what is just, what he does is good:
but it will not be the work of a perfect virtue unless he do it well,
i. e. by choosing rightly, which is the result of prudence; for which
reason justice cannot be a perfect virtue without prudence.
Accordingly faith and hope can exist indeed in a fashion without
charity: but they have not the perfect character of virtue without
charity. For, since the act of faith is to believe in God; and since to
believe is to assent to someone of one's own free will: to will not as
one ought, will not be a perfect act of faith. To will as one ought is
the outcome of charity which perfects the will: since every right
movement of the will proceeds from a right love, as Augustine says (De
Civ. Dei xiv, 9). Hence faith may be without charity, but not as a
perfect virtue: just as temperance and fortitude can be without
prudence. The same applies to hope. Because the act of hope consists in
looking to God for future bliss. This act is perfect, if it is based on
the merits which we have; and this cannot be without charity. But to
expect future bliss through merits which one has not yet, but which one
proposes to acquire at some future time, will be an imperfect act; and
this is possible without charity. Consequently, faith and hope can be
without charity; yet, without charity, they are not virtues properly
so-called; because the nature of virtue requires that by it, we should
not only do what is good, but also that we should do it well (Ethic.
ii, 6).
Reply to Objection 1: Moral virtue depends on prudence: and not even
infused prudence has the character of prudence without charity; for
this involves the absence of due order to the first principle, viz. the
ultimate end. On the other hand faith and hope, as such, do not depend
either on prudence or charity; so that they can be without charity,
although they are not virtues without charity, as stated.
Reply to Objection 2: This argument is true of faith considered as a
perfect virtue.
Reply to Objection 3: Augustine is speaking here of that hope whereby
we look to gain future bliss through merits which we have already; and
this is not without charity.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether charity can be without faith and hope?
Objection 1: It would seem that charity can be without faith and hope.
For charity is the love of God. But it is possible for us to love God
naturally, without already having faith, or hope in future bliss.
Therefore charity can be without faith and hope.
Objection 2: Further, charity is the root of all the virtues, according
to Eph. 3:17: "Rooted and founded in charity. " Now the root is
sometimes without branches. Therefore charity can sometimes be without
faith and hope, and the other virtues.
Objection 3: Further, there was perfect charity in Christ. And yet He
had neither faith nor hope: because He was a perfect comprehensor, as
we shall explain further on ([1611]TP, Q[7], AA[3],4). Therefore
charity can be without faith and hope.
On the contrary, The Apostle says (Heb. 11:6): "Without faith it is
impossible to please God"; and this evidently belongs most to charity,
according to Prov. 8:17: "I love them that love me. " Again, it is by
hope that we are brought to charity, as stated above ([1612]Q[62],
A[4]). Therefore it is not possible to have charity without faith and
hope.
I answer that, Charity signifies not only the love of God, but also a
certain friendship with Him; which implies, besides love, a certain
mutual return of love, together with mutual communion, as stated in
Ethic. viii, 2. That this belongs to charity is evident from 1 Jn.
4:16: "He that abideth in charity, abideth in God, and God in him," and
from 1 Cor. 1:9, where it is written: "God is faithful, by Whom you are
called unto the fellowship of His Son. " Now this fellowship of man with
God, which consists in a certain familiar colloquy with Him, is begun
here, in this life, by grace, but will be perfected in the future life,
by glory; each of which things we hold by faith and hope. Wherefore
just as friendship with a person would be impossible, if one
disbelieved in, or despaired of, the possibility of their fellowship or
familiar colloquy; so too, friendship with God, which is charity, is
impossible without faith, so as to believe in this fellowship and
colloquy with God, and to hope to attain to this fellowship. Therefore
charity is quite impossible without faith and hope.
Reply to Objection 1: Charity is not any kind of love of God, but that
love of God, by which He is loved as the object of bliss, to which
object we are directed by faith and hope.
Reply to Objection 2: Charity is the root of faith and hope, in so far
as it gives them the perfection of virtue. But faith and hope as such
are the precursors of charity, as stated above ([1613]Q[62], A[4]), and
so charity is impossible without them.
Reply to Objection 3: In Christ there was neither faith nor hope, on
account of their implying an imperfection. But instead of faith, He had
manifest vision, and instead of hope, full comprehension [*See
above[1614], Q[4], A[3]]: so that in Him was perfect charity.
__________________________________________________________________
OF EQUALITY AMONG THE VIRTUES (SIX ARTICLES)
We must now consider equality among the virtues: under which head there
are six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether one virtue can be greater or less than another?
(2) Whether all the virtues existing together in one subject are equal?
(3) Of moral virtue in comparison with intellectual virtue;
(4) Of the moral virtues as compared with one another;
(5) Of the intellectual virtues in comparison with one another;
(6) Of the theological virtues in comparison with one another.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether one virtue can be greater or less than another?
Objection 1: It would seem that one virtue cannot be greater or less
than another. For it is written (Apoc. 21:16) that the sides of the
city of Jerusalem are equal; and a gloss says that the sides denote the
virtues. Therefore all virtues are equal; and consequently one cannot
be greater than another.
Objection 2: Further, a thing that, by its nature, consists in a
maximum, cannot be more or less. Now the nature of virtue consists in a
maximum, for virtue is "the limit of power," as the Philosopher states
(De Coelo i, text. 116); and Augustine says (De Lib. Arb. ii, 19) that
"virtues are very great boons, and no one can use them to evil
purpose. " Therefore it seems that one virtue cannot be greater or less
than another.
Objection 3: Further, the quantity of an effect is measured by the
power of the agent. But perfect, viz. infused virtues, are from God
Whose power is uniform and infinite. Therefore it seems that one virtue
cannot be greater than another.
On the contrary, Wherever there can be increase and greater abundance,
there can be inequality.
Now virtues admit of greater abundance and
increase: for it is written (Mat. 5:20): "Unless your justice abound
more than that of the Scribes and Pharisees, you shall not enter into
the kingdom of heaven": and (Prov. 15:5): "In abundant justice there is
the greatest strength [virtus]. " Therefore it seems that a virtue can
be greater or less than another.
I answer that, When it is asked whether one virtue can be greater than
another, the question can be taken in two senses. First, as applying to
virtues of different species. In this sense it is clear that one virtue
is greater than another; since a cause is always more excellent than
its effect; and among effects, those nearest to the cause are the most
excellent. Now it is clear from what has been said ([1615]Q[18],
A[5];[1616] Q[61], A[2]) that the cause and root of human good is the
reason. Hence prudence which perfects the reason, surpasses in goodness
the other moral virtues which perfect the appetitive power, in so far
as it partakes of reason. And among these, one is better than another,
according as it approaches nearer to the reason. Consequently justice,
which is in the will, excels the remaining moral virtues; and
fortitude, which is in the irascible part, stands before temperance,
which is in the concupiscible, which has a smaller share of reason, as
stated in Ethic. vii, 6.
The question can be taken in another way, as referring to virtues of
the same species. In this way, according to what was said above
([1617]Q[52], A[1] ), when we were treating of the intensity of habits,
virtue may be said to be greater or less in two ways: first, in itself;
secondly with regard to the subject that partakes of it. If we consider
it in itself, we shall call it greater or little, according to the
things to which it extends. Now whosoever has a virtue, e. g.
temperance, has it in respect of whatever temperance extends to. But
this does not apply to science and art: for every grammarian does not
know everything relating to grammar. And in this sense the Stoics said
rightly, as Simplicius states in his Commentary on the Predicaments,
that virtue cannot be more or less, as science and art can; because the
nature of virtue consists in a maximum.
If, however, we consider virtue on the part of the subject, it may then
be greater or less, either in relation to different times, or in
different men. Because one man is better disposed than another to
attain to the mean of virtue which is defined by right reason; and
this, on account of either greater habituation, or a better natural
disposition, or a more discerning judgment of reason, or again a
greater gift of grace, which is given to each one "according to the
measure of the giving of Christ," as stated in Eph. 4:9. And here the
Stoics erred, for they held that no man should be deemed virtuous,
unless he were, in the highest degree, disposed to virtue. Because the
nature of virtue does not require that man should reach the mean of
right reason as though it were an indivisible point, as the Stoics
thought; but it is enough that he should approach the mean, as stated
in Ethic. ii, 6. Moreover, one same indivisible mark is reached more
nearly and more readily by one than by another: as may be seen when
several arches aim at a fixed target.
Reply to Objection 1: This equality is not one of absolute quantity,
but of proportion: because all virtues grow in a man proportionately,
as we shall see further on [1618](A[2]).
Reply to Objection 2: This "limit" which belongs to virtue, can have
the character of something "more" or "less" good, in the ways explained
above: since, as stated, it is not an indivisible limit.
Reply to Objection 3: God does not work by necessity of nature, but
according to the order of His wisdom, whereby He bestows on men various
measures of virtue, according to Eph. 4:7: "To every one of you [Vulg. :
'us'] is given grace according to the measure of the giving of Christ. "
__________________________________________________________________
Whether all the virtues that are together in one man, are equal?
Objection 1: It would seem that the virtues in one same man are not all
equally intense. For the Apostle says (1 Cor. 7:7): "Everyone hath his
proper gift from God; one after this manner, and another after that. "
Now one gift would not be more proper than another to a man, if God
infused all the virtues equally into each man. Therefore it seems that
the virtues are not all equal in one and the same man.
Objection 2: Further, if all the virtues were equally intense in one
and the same man, it would follow that whoever surpasses another in one
virtue, would surpass him in all the others. But this is clearly not
the case: since various saints are specially praised for different
virtues; e. g. Abraham for faith (Rom. 4), Moses for his meekness (Num.
7:3), Job for his patience (Tob. 2:12). This is why of each Confessor
the Church sings: "There was not found his like in keeping the law of
the most High," [*See Lesson in the Mass Statuit (Dominican Missal)],
since each one was remarkable for some virtue or other. Therefore the
virtues are not all equal in one and the same man.
Objection 3: Further, the more intense a habit is, the greater one's
pleasure and readiness in making use of it. Now experience shows that a
man is more pleased and ready to make use of one virtue than of
another. Therefore the virtues are not all equal in one and the same
man.
On the contrary, Augustine says (De Trin. vi, 4) that "those who are
equal in fortitude are equal in prudence and temperance," and so on.
Now it would not be so, unless all the virtues in one man were equal.
Therefore all virtues are equal in one man.
I answer that, As explained above [1619](A[1]), the comparative
greatness of virtues can be understood in two ways. First, as referring
to their specific nature: and in this way there is no doubt that in a
man one virtue is greater than another, for example, charity, than
faith and hope. Secondly, it may be taken as referring to the degree of
participation by the subject, according as a virtue becomes intense or
remiss in its subject. In this sense all the virtues in one man are
equal with an equality of proportion, in so far as their growth in man
is equal: thus the fingers are unequal in size, but equal in
proportion, since they grow in proportion to one another.
Now the nature of this equality is to be explained in the same way as
the connection of virtues; for equality among virtues is their
connection as to greatness. Now it has been stated above ([1620]Q[65],
A[1]) that a twofold connection of virtues may be assigned. The first
is according to the opinion of those who understood these four virtues
to be four general properties of virtues, each of which is found
together with the other in any matter. In this way virtues cannot be
said to be equal in any matter unless they have all these properties
equal. Augustine alludes to this kind of equality (De Trin. vi, 4) when
he says: "If you say these men are equal in fortitude, but that one is
more prudent than the other; it follows that the fortitude of the
latter is less prudent. Consequently they are not really equal in
fortitude, since the former's fortitude is more prudent. You will find
that this applies to the other virtues if you run over them all in the
same way. "
The other kind of connection among virtues followed the opinion of
those who hold these virtues to have their own proper respective
matters ([1621]Q[65] , AA[1],2). In this way the connection among moral
virtues results from prudence, and, as to the infused virtues, from
charity, and not from the inclination, which is on the part of the
subject, as stated above ([1622]Q[65], A[1]). Accordingly the nature of
the equality among virtues can also be considered on the part of
prudence, in regard to that which is formal in all the moral virtues:
for in one and the same man, so long as his reason has the same degree
of perfection, the mean will be proportionately defined according to
right reason in each matter of virtue.
But in regard to that which is material in the moral virtues, viz. the
inclination to the virtuous act, one may be readier to perform the act
of one virtue, than the act of another virtue, and this either from
nature, or from habituation, or again by the grace of God.
Reply to Objection 1: This saying of the Apostle may be taken to refer
to the gifts of gratuitous grace, which are not common to all, nor are
all of them equal in the one same subject. We might also say that it
refers to the measure of sanctifying grace, by reason of which one man
has all the virtues in greater abundance than another man, on account
of his greater abundance of prudence, or also of charity, in which all
the infused virtues are connected.
Reply to Objection 2: One saint is praised chiefly for one virtue,
another saint for another virtue, on account of his more admirable
readiness for the act of one virtue than for the act of another virtue.
This suffices for the Reply to the Third Objection.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether the moral virtues are better than the intellectual virtues?
Objection 1: It would seem that the moral virtues are better than the
intellectual. Because that which is more necessary, and more lasting,
is better. Now the moral virtues are "more lasting even than the
sciences" (Ethic. i) which are intellectual virtues: and, moreover,
they are more necessary for human life. Therefore they are preferable
to the intellectual virtues.
Objection 2: Further, virtue is defined as "that which makes its
possessor good. " Now man is said to be good in respect of moral virtue,
and art in respect of intellectual virtue, except perhaps in respect of
prudence alone. Therefore moral is better than intellectual virtue.
Objection 3: Further, the end is more excellent than the means. But
according to Ethic. vi, 12, "moral virtue gives right intention of the
end; whereas prudence gives right choice of the means. " Therefore moral
virtue is more excellent than prudence, which is the intellectual
virtue that regards moral matters.
On the contrary, Moral virtue is in that part of the soul which is
rational by participation; while intellectual virtue is in the
essentially rational part, as stated in Ethic. i, 13. Now rational by
essence is more excellent than rational by participation. Therefore
intellectual virtue is better than moral virtue.
I answer that, A thing may be said to be greater or less in two ways:
first, simply; secondly, relatively. For nothing hinders something from
being better simply, e. g. "learning than riches," and yet not better
relatively, i. e. "for one who is in want" [*Aristotle, Topic. iii. ].
Now to consider a thing simply is to consider it in its proper specific
nature. Accordingly, a virtue takes its species from its object, as
explained above ([1623]Q[54], A[2];[1624] Q[60], A[1]). Hence, speaking
simply, that virtue is more excellent, which has the more excellent
object. Now it is evident that the object of the reason is more
excellent than the object of the appetite: since the reason apprehends
things in the universal, while the appetite tends to things themselves,
whose being is restricted to the particular. Consequently, speaking
simply, the intellectual virtues, which perfect the reason, are more
excellent than the moral virtues, which perfect the appetite.
But if we consider virtue in its relation to act, then moral virtue,
which perfects the appetite, whose function it is to move the other
powers to act, as stated above ([1625]Q[9], A[1]), is more excellent.
And since virtue is so called from its being a principle of action, for
it is the perfection of a power, it follows again that the nature of
virtue agrees more with moral than with intellectual virtue, though the
intellectual virtues are more excellent habits, simply speaking.
Reply to Objection 1: The moral virtues are more lasting than the
intellectual virtues, because they are practised in matters pertaining
to the life of the community. Yet it is evident that the objects of the
sciences, which are necessary and invariable, are more lasting than the
objects of moral virtue, which are certain particular matters of
action. That the moral virtues are more necessary for human life,
proves that they are more excellent, not simply, but relatively.
Indeed, the speculative intellectual virtues, from the very fact that
they are not referred to something else, as a useful thing is referred
to an end, are more excellent. The reason for this is that in them we
have a kind of beginning of that happiness which consists in the
knowledge of truth, as stated above ([1626]Q[3], A[6]).
Reply to Objection 2: The reason why man is said to be good simply, in
respect of moral virtue, but not in respect of intellectual virtue, is
because the appetite moves the other powers to their acts, as stated
above ([1627]Q[56], A[3]). Wherefore this argument, too, proves merely
that moral virtue is better relatively.
Reply to Objection 3: Prudence directs the moral virtues not only in
the choice of the means, but also in appointing the end. Now the end of
each moral virtue is to attain the mean in the matter proper to that
virtue; which mean is appointed according to the right ruling of
prudence, as stated in Ethic. ii, 6; vi, 13.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether justice is the chief of the moral virtues?
Objection 1: It would seem that justice is not the chief of the moral
virtues. For it is better to give of one's own than to pay what is due.
Now the former belongs to liberality, the latter to justice. Therefore
liberality is apparently a greater virtue than justice.
Objection 2: Further, the chief quality of a thing is, seemingly, that
in which it is most perfect. Now, according to Jam. 1:4, "Patience hath
a perfect work. " Therefore it would seem that patience is greater than
justice.
Objection 3: Further, "Magnanimity has a great influence on every
virtue," as stated in Ethic. iv, 3. Therefore it magnifies even
justice. Therefore it is greater than justice.
On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Ethic. v, 1) that "justice is
the most excellent of the virtues. "
I answer that, A virtue considered in its species may be greater or
less, either simply or relatively. A virtue is said to be greater
simply, whereby a greater rational good shines forth, as stated above
[1628](A[1]). In this way justice is the most excellent of all the
moral virtues, as being most akin to reason. This is made evident by
considering its subject and its object: its subject, because this is
the will, and the will is the rational appetite, as stated above (Q[8],
A[1]; Q[26], A[1]): its object or matter, because it is about
operations, whereby man is set in order not only in himself, but also
in regard to another. Hence "justice is the most excellent of virtues"
(Ethic. v, 1). Among the other moral virtues, which are about the
passions, the more excellent the matter in which the appetitive
movement is subjected to reason, so much the more does the rational
good shine forth in each. Now in things touching man, the chief of all
is life, on which all other things depend. Consequently fortitude which
subjects the appetitive movement to reason in matters of life and
death, holds the first place among those moral virtues that are about
the passions, but is subordinate to justice. Hence the Philosopher says
(Rhet. 1) that "those virtues must needs be greatest which receive the
most praise: since virtue is a power of doing good. Hence the brave man
and the just man are honored more than others; because the former,"
i. e. fortitude, "is useful in war, and the latter," i. e. justice, "both
in war and in peace. " After fortitude comes temperance, which subjects
the appetite to reason in matters directly relating to life, in the one
individual, or in the one species, viz. in matters of food and of sex.
And so these three virtues, together with prudence, are called
principal virtues, in excellence also.
A virtue is said to be greater relatively, by reason of its helping or
adorning a principal virtue: even as substance is more excellent simply
than accident: and yet relatively some particular accident is more
excellent than substance in so far as it perfects substance in some
accidental mode of being.
Reply to Objection 1: The act of liberality needs to be founded on an
act of justice, for "a man is not liberal in giving, unless he gives of
his own" (Polit. ii, 3). Hence there could be no liberality apart from
justice, which discerns between "meum" and "tuum": whereas justice can
be without liberality. Hence justice is simply greater than liberality,
as being more universal, and as being its foundation: while liberality
is greater relatively since it is an ornament and an addition to
justice.
Reply to Objection 2: Patience is said to have "a perfect work," by
enduring evils, wherein it excludes not only unjust revenge, which is
also excluded by justice; not only hatred, which is also suppressed by
charity; nor only anger, which is calmed by gentleness; but also
inordinate sorrow, which is the root of all the above. Wherefore it is
more perfect and excellent through plucking up the root in this matter.
It is not, however, more perfect than all the other virtues simply.
Because fortitude not only endures trouble without being disturbed, but
also fights against it if necessary. Hence whoever is brave is patient;
but the converse does not hold, for patience is a part of fortitude.
Reply to Objection 3: There can be no magnanimity without the other
virtues, as stated in Ethic. iv, 3. Hence it is compared to them as
their ornament, so that relatively it is greater than all the others,
but not simply.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether wisdom is the greatest of the intellectual virtues?
Objection 1: It would seem that wisdom is not the greatest of the
intellectual virtues. Because the commander is greater than the one
commanded. Now prudence seems to command wisdom, for it is stated in
Ethic. i, 2 that political science, which belongs to prudence (Ethic.
vi, 8), "orders that sciences should be cultivated in states, and to
which of these each individual should devote himself, and to what
extent. " Since, then, wisdom is one of the sciences, it seems that
prudence is greater than wisdom.
Objection 2: Further, it belongs to the nature of virtue to direct man
to happiness: because virtue is "the disposition of a perfect thing to
that which is best," as stated in Phys. vii, text. 17. Now prudence is
"right reason about things to be done," whereby man is brought to
happiness: whereas wisdom takes no notice of human acts, whereby man
attains happiness. Therefore prudence is a greater virtue than wisdom.
Objection 3: Further, the more perfect knowledge is, the greater it
seems to be. Now we can have more perfect knowledge of human affairs,
which are the subject of science, than of Divine things, which are the
object of wisdom, which is the distinction given by Augustine (De Trin.
xii, 14): because Divine things are incomprehensible, according to Job
26:26: "Behold God is great, exceeding our knowledge. " Therefore
science is a greater virtue than wisdom.
Objection 4: Further, knowledge of principles is more excellent than
knowledge of conclusions. But wisdom draws conclusions from
indemonstrable principles which are the object of the virtue of
understanding, even as other sciences do. Therefore understanding is a
greater virtue than wisdom.
On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Ethic. vi, 7) that wisdom is
"the head" among "the intellectual virtues. "
I answer that, As stated above [1629](A[3]), the greatness of a virtue,
as to its species, is taken from its object. Now the object of wisdom
surpasses the objects of all the intellectual virtues: because wisdom
considers the Supreme Cause, which is God, as stated at the beginning
of the Metaphysics. And since it is by the cause that we judge of an
effect, and by the higher cause that we judge of the lower effects;
hence it is that wisdom exercises judgment over all the other
intellectual virtues, directs them all, and is the architect of them
all.
Reply to Objection 1: Since prudence is about human affairs, and wisdom
about the Supreme Cause, it is impossible for prudence to be a greater
virtue than wisdom, "unless," as stated in Ethic. vi, 7, "man were the
greatest thing in the world. " Wherefore we must say, as stated in the
same book (Ethic. vi), that prudence does not command wisdom, but vice
versa: because "the spiritual man judgeth all things; and he himself is
judged by no man" (1 Cor. 2:15). For prudence has no business with
supreme matters which are the object of wisdom: but its command covers
things directed to wisdom, viz. how men are to obtain wisdom. Wherefore
prudence, or political science, is, in this way, the servant of wisdom;
for it leads to wisdom, preparing the way for her, as the doorkeeper
for the king.
Reply to Objection 2: Prudence considers the means of acquiring
happiness, but wisdom considers the very object of happiness, viz. the
Supreme Intelligible. And if indeed the consideration of wisdom were
perfect in respect of its object, there would be perfect happiness in
the act of wisdom: but as, in this life, the act of wisdom is imperfect
in respect of its principal object, which is God, it follows that the
act of wisdom is a beginning or participation of future happiness, so
that wisdom is nearer than prudence to happiness.
Reply to Objection 3: As the Philosopher says (De Anima i, text. 1),
"one knowledge is preferable to another, either because it is about a
higher object, or because it is more certain.
OBJ[1]). Augustine also gives the same reason (De Trin. vi, 4).
Others, however, differentiate these virtues in respect of their
matters, and it is in this way that Aristotle assigns the reason for
their connection (Ethic. vi, 13). Because, as stated above
([1606]Q[58], A[4]), no moral virtue can be without prudence; since it
is proper to moral virtue to make a right choice, for it is an elective
habit. Now right choice requires not only the inclination to a due end,
which inclination is the direct outcome of moral virtue, but also
correct choice of things conducive to the end, which choice is made by
prudence, that counsels, judges, and commands in those things that are
directed to the end. In like manner one cannot have prudence unless one
has the moral virtues: since prudence is "right reason about things to
be done," and the starting point of reason is the end of the thing to
be done, to which end man is rightly disposed by moral virtue. Hence,
just as we cannot have speculative science unless we have the
understanding of the principles, so neither can we have prudence
without the moral virtues: and from this it follows clearly that the
moral virtues are connected with one another.
Reply to Objection 1: Some moral virtues perfect man as regards his
general state, in other words, with regard to those things which have
to be done in every kind of human life. Hence man needs to exercise
himself at the same time in the matters of all moral virtues. And if he
exercise himself, by good deeds, in all such matters, he will acquire
the habits of all the moral virtues. But if he exercise himself by good
deeds in regard to one matter, but not in regard to another, for
instance, by behaving well in matters of anger, but not in matters of
concupiscence; he will indeed acquire a certain habit of restraining
his anger; but this habit will lack the nature of virtue, through the
absence of prudence, which is wanting in matters of concupiscence. In
the same way, natural inclinations fail to have the complete character
of virtue, if prudence be lacking.
But there are some moral virtues which perfect man with regard to some
eminent state, such as magnificence and magnanimity; and since it does
not happen to all in common to be exercised in the matter of such
virtues, it is possible for a man to have the other moral virtues,
without actually having the habits of these virtues---provided we speak
of acquired virtue. Nevertheless, when once a man has acquired those
other virtues he possesses these in proximate potentiality. Because
when, by practice, a man has acquired liberality in small gifts and
expenditure, if he were to come in for a large sum of money, he would
acquire the habit of magnificence with but little practice: even as a
geometrician, by dint of little study, acquires scientific knowledge
about some conclusion which had never been presented to his mind
before. Now we speak of having a thing when we are on the point of
having it, according to the saying of the Philosopher (Phys. ii, text.
56): "That which is scarcely lacking is not lacking at all. "
This suffices for the Reply to the Second Objection.
Reply to Objection 3: The intellectual virtues are about divers matters
having no relation to one another, as is clearly the case with the
various sciences and arts. Hence we do not observe in them the
connection that is to be found among the moral virtues, which are about
passions and operations, that are clearly related to one another. For
all the passions have their rise in certain initial passions, viz. love
and hatred, and terminate in certain others, viz. pleasure and sorrow.
In like manner all the operations that are the matter of moral virtue
are related to one another, and to the passions. Hence the whole matter
of moral virtues falls under the one rule of prudence.
Nevertheless, all intelligible things are related to first principles.
And in this way, all the intellectual virtues depend on the
understanding of principles; even as prudence depends on the moral
virtues, as stated. On the other hand, the universal principles which
are the object of the virtue of understanding of principles, do not
depend on the conclusions, which are the objects of the other
intellectual virtues, as do the moral virtues depend on prudence,
because the appetite, in a fashion, moves the reason, and the reason
the appetite, as stated above ([1607]Q[9], A[1];[1608] Q[58], A[5], ad
1).
Reply to Objection 4: Those things to which the moral virtues incline,
are as the principles of prudence: whereas the products of art are not
the principles, but the matter of art. Now it is evident that, though
reason may be right in one part of the matter, and not in another, yet
in no way can it be called right reason, if it be deficient in any
principle whatever. Thus, if a man be wrong about the principle, "A
whole is greater than its part," he cannot acquire the science of
geometry, because he must necessarily wander from the truth in his
conclusion. Moreover, things "done" are related to one another, but not
things "made," as stated above (ad 3). Consequently the lack of
prudence in one department of things to be done, would result in a
deficiency affecting other things to be done: whereas this does not
occur in things to be made.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether moral virtues can be without charity?
Objection 1: It would seem that moral virtues can be without charity.
For it is stated in the Liber Sentent. Prosperi vii, that "every virtue
save charity may be common to the good and bad. " But "charity can be in
none except the good," as stated in the same book. Therefore the other
virtues can be had without charity.
Objection 2: Further, moral virtues can be acquired by means of human
acts, as stated in Ethic. ii, 1,2, whereas charity cannot be had
otherwise than by infusion, according to Rom. 5:5: "The charity of God
is poured forth in our hearts by the Holy Ghost Who is given to us. "
Therefore it is possible to have the other virtues without charity.
Objection 3: Further, the moral virtues are connected together, through
depending on prudence. But charity does not depend on prudence; indeed,
it surpasses prudence, according to Eph. 3:19: "The charity of Christ,
which surpasseth all knowledge. " Therefore the moral virtues are not
connected with charity, and can be without it.
On the contrary, It is written (1 Jn. 3:14): "He that loveth not,
abideth in death. " Now the spiritual life is perfected by the virtues,
since it is "by them" that "we lead a good life," as Augustine states
(De Lib. Arb. ii, 17,19). Therefore they cannot be without the love of
charity.
I answer that, As stated above (Q[63], A[2]), it is possible by means
of human works to acquire moral virtues, in so far as they produce good
works that are directed to an end not surpassing the natural power of
man: and when they are acquired thus, they can be without charity, even
as they were in many of the Gentiles. But in so far as they produce
good works in proportion to a supernatural last end, thus they have the
character of virtue, truly and perfectly; and cannot be acquired by
human acts, but are infused by God. Such like moral virtues cannot be
without charity. For it has been stated above [1609](A[1]; Q[58],
AA[4],5) that the other moral virtues cannot be without prudence; and
that prudence cannot be without the moral virtues, because these latter
make man well disposed to certain ends, which are the starting-point of
the procedure of prudence. Now for prudence to proceed aright, it is
much more necessary that man be well disposed towards his ultimate end,
which is the effect of charity, than that he be well disposed in
respect of other ends, which is the effect of moral virtue: just as in
speculative matters right reason has greatest need of the first
indemonstrable principle, that "contradictories cannot both be true at
the same time. " It is therefore evident that neither can infused
prudence be without charity; nor, consequently, the other moral
virtues, since they cannot be without prudence.
It is therefore clear from what has been said that only the infused
virtues are perfect, and deserve to be called virtues simply: since
they direct man well to the ultimate end. But the other virtues, those,
namely, that are acquired, are virtues in a restricted sense, but not
simply: for they direct man well in respect of the last end in some
particular genus of action, but not in respect of the last end simply.
Hence a gloss of Augustine [*Cf. Lib. Sentent. Prosperi cvi. ] on the
words, "All that is not of faith is sin" (Rom. 14:23), says: "He that
fails to acknowledge the truth, has no true virtue, even if his conduct
be good. "
Reply to Objection 1: Virtue, in the words quoted, denotes imperfect
virtue. Else if we take moral virtue in its perfect state, "it makes
its possessor good," and consequently cannot be in the wicked.
Reply to Objection 2: This argument holds good of virtue in the sense
of acquired virtue.
Reply to Objection 3: Though charity surpasses science and prudence,
yet prudence depends on charity, as stated: and consequently so do all
the infused moral virtues.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether charity can be without moral virtue?
Objection 1: It would seem possible to have charity without the moral
virtues. For when one thing suffices for a certain purpose, it is
superfluous to employ others. Now charity alone suffices for the
fulfilment of all the works of virtue, as is clear from 1 Cor. 13:4,
seqq. : "Charity is patient, is kind," etc. Therefore it seems that if
one has charity, other virtues are superfluous.
Objection 2: Further, he that has a habit of virtue easily performs the
works of that virtue, and those works are pleasing to him for their own
sake: hence "pleasure taken in a work is a sign of habit" (Ethic. ii,
3). Now many have charity, being free from mortal sin, and yet they
find it difficult to do works of virtue; nor are these works pleasing
to them for their own sake, but only for the sake of charity. Therefore
many have charity without the other virtues.
Objection 3: Further, charity is to be found in every saint: and yet
there are some saints who are without certain virtues. For Bede says
(on Lk. 17:10) that the saints are more humbled on account of their not
having certain virtues, than rejoiced at the virtues they have.
Therefore, if a man has charity, it does not follow of necessity that
he has all the moral virtues.
On the contrary, The whole Law is fulfilled through charity, for it is
written (Rom. 13:8): "He that loveth his neighbor, hath fulfilled the
Law. " Now it is not possible to fulfil the whole Law, without having
all the moral virtues: since the law contains precepts about all acts
of virtue, as stated in Ethic. v, 1,2. Therefore he that has charity,
has all the moral virtues. Moreover, Augustine says in a letter (Epis.
clxvii) [*Cf. Serm. xxxix and xlvi de Temp. ] that charity contains all
the cardinal virtues.
I answer that, All the moral virtues are infused together with charity.
The reason for this is that God operates no less perfectly in works of
grace than in works of nature. Now, in the works of nature, we find
that whenever a thing contains a principle of certain works, it has
also whatever is necessary for their execution: thus animals are
provided with organs whereby to perform the actions that their souls
empower them to do. Now it is evident that charity, inasmuch as it
directs man to his last end, is the principle of all the good works
that are referable to his last end. Wherefore all the moral virtues
must needs be infused together with charity, since it is through them
that man performs each different kind of good work.
It is therefore clear that the infused moral virtues are connected, not
only through prudence, but also on account of charity: and, again, that
whoever loses charity through mortal sin, forfeits all the infused
moral virtues.
Reply to Objection 1: In order that the act of a lower power be
perfect, not only must there be perfection in the higher, but also in
the lower power: for if the principal agent were well disposed, perfect
action would not follow, if the instrument also were not well disposed.
Consequently, in order that man work well in things referred to the
end, he needs not only a virtue disposing him well to the end, but also
those virtues which dispose him well to whatever is referred to the
end: for the virtue which regards the end is the chief and moving
principle in respect of those things that are referred to the end.
Therefore it is necessary to have the moral virtues together with
charity.
Reply to Objection 2: It happens sometimes that a man who has a habit,
finds it difficult to act in accordance with the habit, and
consequently feels no pleasure and complacency in the act, on account
of some impediment supervening from without: thus a man who has a habit
of science, finds it difficult to understand, through being sleepy or
unwell. In like manner sometimes the habits of moral virtue experience
difficulty in their works, by reason of certain ordinary dispositions
remaining from previous acts. This difficulty does not occur in respect
of acquired moral virtue: because the repeated acts by which they are
acquired, remove also the contrary dispositions.
Reply to Objection 3: Certain saints are said not to have certain
virtues, in so far as they experience difficulty in the acts of those
virtues, for the reason stated; although they have the habits of all
the virtues.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether faith and hope can be without charity?
Objection 1: It would seem that faith and hope are never without
charity. Because, since they are theological virtues, they seem to be
more excellent than even the infused moral virtues. But the infused
moral virtues cannot be without charity. Neither therefore can faith
and hope be without charity.
Objection 2: Further, "no man believes unwillingly" as Augustine says
(Tract. xxvi in Joan. ). But charity is in the will as a perfection
thereof, as stated above ([1610]Q[62], A[3]). Therefore faith cannot be
without charity.
Objection 3: Further, Augustine says (Enchiridion viii) that "there can
be no hope without love. " But love is charity: for it is of this love
that he speaks. Therefore hope cannot be without charity.
On the contrary, A gloss on Mat. 1:2 says that "faith begets hope, and
hope, charity. " Now the begetter precedes the begotten, and can be
without it. Therefore faith can be without hope; and hope, without
charity.
I answer that, Faith and hope, like the moral virtues, can be
considered in two ways; first in an inchoate state; secondly, as
complete virtues. For since virtue is directed to the doing of good
works, perfect virtue is that which gives the faculty of doing a
perfectly good work, and this consists in not only doing what is good,
but also in doing it well. Else, if what is done is good, but not well
done, it will not be perfectly good; wherefore neither will the habit
that is the principle of such an act, have the perfect character of
virtue. For instance, if a man do what is just, what he does is good:
but it will not be the work of a perfect virtue unless he do it well,
i. e. by choosing rightly, which is the result of prudence; for which
reason justice cannot be a perfect virtue without prudence.
Accordingly faith and hope can exist indeed in a fashion without
charity: but they have not the perfect character of virtue without
charity. For, since the act of faith is to believe in God; and since to
believe is to assent to someone of one's own free will: to will not as
one ought, will not be a perfect act of faith. To will as one ought is
the outcome of charity which perfects the will: since every right
movement of the will proceeds from a right love, as Augustine says (De
Civ. Dei xiv, 9). Hence faith may be without charity, but not as a
perfect virtue: just as temperance and fortitude can be without
prudence. The same applies to hope. Because the act of hope consists in
looking to God for future bliss. This act is perfect, if it is based on
the merits which we have; and this cannot be without charity. But to
expect future bliss through merits which one has not yet, but which one
proposes to acquire at some future time, will be an imperfect act; and
this is possible without charity. Consequently, faith and hope can be
without charity; yet, without charity, they are not virtues properly
so-called; because the nature of virtue requires that by it, we should
not only do what is good, but also that we should do it well (Ethic.
ii, 6).
Reply to Objection 1: Moral virtue depends on prudence: and not even
infused prudence has the character of prudence without charity; for
this involves the absence of due order to the first principle, viz. the
ultimate end. On the other hand faith and hope, as such, do not depend
either on prudence or charity; so that they can be without charity,
although they are not virtues without charity, as stated.
Reply to Objection 2: This argument is true of faith considered as a
perfect virtue.
Reply to Objection 3: Augustine is speaking here of that hope whereby
we look to gain future bliss through merits which we have already; and
this is not without charity.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether charity can be without faith and hope?
Objection 1: It would seem that charity can be without faith and hope.
For charity is the love of God. But it is possible for us to love God
naturally, without already having faith, or hope in future bliss.
Therefore charity can be without faith and hope.
Objection 2: Further, charity is the root of all the virtues, according
to Eph. 3:17: "Rooted and founded in charity. " Now the root is
sometimes without branches. Therefore charity can sometimes be without
faith and hope, and the other virtues.
Objection 3: Further, there was perfect charity in Christ. And yet He
had neither faith nor hope: because He was a perfect comprehensor, as
we shall explain further on ([1611]TP, Q[7], AA[3],4). Therefore
charity can be without faith and hope.
On the contrary, The Apostle says (Heb. 11:6): "Without faith it is
impossible to please God"; and this evidently belongs most to charity,
according to Prov. 8:17: "I love them that love me. " Again, it is by
hope that we are brought to charity, as stated above ([1612]Q[62],
A[4]). Therefore it is not possible to have charity without faith and
hope.
I answer that, Charity signifies not only the love of God, but also a
certain friendship with Him; which implies, besides love, a certain
mutual return of love, together with mutual communion, as stated in
Ethic. viii, 2. That this belongs to charity is evident from 1 Jn.
4:16: "He that abideth in charity, abideth in God, and God in him," and
from 1 Cor. 1:9, where it is written: "God is faithful, by Whom you are
called unto the fellowship of His Son. " Now this fellowship of man with
God, which consists in a certain familiar colloquy with Him, is begun
here, in this life, by grace, but will be perfected in the future life,
by glory; each of which things we hold by faith and hope. Wherefore
just as friendship with a person would be impossible, if one
disbelieved in, or despaired of, the possibility of their fellowship or
familiar colloquy; so too, friendship with God, which is charity, is
impossible without faith, so as to believe in this fellowship and
colloquy with God, and to hope to attain to this fellowship. Therefore
charity is quite impossible without faith and hope.
Reply to Objection 1: Charity is not any kind of love of God, but that
love of God, by which He is loved as the object of bliss, to which
object we are directed by faith and hope.
Reply to Objection 2: Charity is the root of faith and hope, in so far
as it gives them the perfection of virtue. But faith and hope as such
are the precursors of charity, as stated above ([1613]Q[62], A[4]), and
so charity is impossible without them.
Reply to Objection 3: In Christ there was neither faith nor hope, on
account of their implying an imperfection. But instead of faith, He had
manifest vision, and instead of hope, full comprehension [*See
above[1614], Q[4], A[3]]: so that in Him was perfect charity.
__________________________________________________________________
OF EQUALITY AMONG THE VIRTUES (SIX ARTICLES)
We must now consider equality among the virtues: under which head there
are six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether one virtue can be greater or less than another?
(2) Whether all the virtues existing together in one subject are equal?
(3) Of moral virtue in comparison with intellectual virtue;
(4) Of the moral virtues as compared with one another;
(5) Of the intellectual virtues in comparison with one another;
(6) Of the theological virtues in comparison with one another.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether one virtue can be greater or less than another?
Objection 1: It would seem that one virtue cannot be greater or less
than another. For it is written (Apoc. 21:16) that the sides of the
city of Jerusalem are equal; and a gloss says that the sides denote the
virtues. Therefore all virtues are equal; and consequently one cannot
be greater than another.
Objection 2: Further, a thing that, by its nature, consists in a
maximum, cannot be more or less. Now the nature of virtue consists in a
maximum, for virtue is "the limit of power," as the Philosopher states
(De Coelo i, text. 116); and Augustine says (De Lib. Arb. ii, 19) that
"virtues are very great boons, and no one can use them to evil
purpose. " Therefore it seems that one virtue cannot be greater or less
than another.
Objection 3: Further, the quantity of an effect is measured by the
power of the agent. But perfect, viz. infused virtues, are from God
Whose power is uniform and infinite. Therefore it seems that one virtue
cannot be greater than another.
On the contrary, Wherever there can be increase and greater abundance,
there can be inequality.
Now virtues admit of greater abundance and
increase: for it is written (Mat. 5:20): "Unless your justice abound
more than that of the Scribes and Pharisees, you shall not enter into
the kingdom of heaven": and (Prov. 15:5): "In abundant justice there is
the greatest strength [virtus]. " Therefore it seems that a virtue can
be greater or less than another.
I answer that, When it is asked whether one virtue can be greater than
another, the question can be taken in two senses. First, as applying to
virtues of different species. In this sense it is clear that one virtue
is greater than another; since a cause is always more excellent than
its effect; and among effects, those nearest to the cause are the most
excellent. Now it is clear from what has been said ([1615]Q[18],
A[5];[1616] Q[61], A[2]) that the cause and root of human good is the
reason. Hence prudence which perfects the reason, surpasses in goodness
the other moral virtues which perfect the appetitive power, in so far
as it partakes of reason. And among these, one is better than another,
according as it approaches nearer to the reason. Consequently justice,
which is in the will, excels the remaining moral virtues; and
fortitude, which is in the irascible part, stands before temperance,
which is in the concupiscible, which has a smaller share of reason, as
stated in Ethic. vii, 6.
The question can be taken in another way, as referring to virtues of
the same species. In this way, according to what was said above
([1617]Q[52], A[1] ), when we were treating of the intensity of habits,
virtue may be said to be greater or less in two ways: first, in itself;
secondly with regard to the subject that partakes of it. If we consider
it in itself, we shall call it greater or little, according to the
things to which it extends. Now whosoever has a virtue, e. g.
temperance, has it in respect of whatever temperance extends to. But
this does not apply to science and art: for every grammarian does not
know everything relating to grammar. And in this sense the Stoics said
rightly, as Simplicius states in his Commentary on the Predicaments,
that virtue cannot be more or less, as science and art can; because the
nature of virtue consists in a maximum.
If, however, we consider virtue on the part of the subject, it may then
be greater or less, either in relation to different times, or in
different men. Because one man is better disposed than another to
attain to the mean of virtue which is defined by right reason; and
this, on account of either greater habituation, or a better natural
disposition, or a more discerning judgment of reason, or again a
greater gift of grace, which is given to each one "according to the
measure of the giving of Christ," as stated in Eph. 4:9. And here the
Stoics erred, for they held that no man should be deemed virtuous,
unless he were, in the highest degree, disposed to virtue. Because the
nature of virtue does not require that man should reach the mean of
right reason as though it were an indivisible point, as the Stoics
thought; but it is enough that he should approach the mean, as stated
in Ethic. ii, 6. Moreover, one same indivisible mark is reached more
nearly and more readily by one than by another: as may be seen when
several arches aim at a fixed target.
Reply to Objection 1: This equality is not one of absolute quantity,
but of proportion: because all virtues grow in a man proportionately,
as we shall see further on [1618](A[2]).
Reply to Objection 2: This "limit" which belongs to virtue, can have
the character of something "more" or "less" good, in the ways explained
above: since, as stated, it is not an indivisible limit.
Reply to Objection 3: God does not work by necessity of nature, but
according to the order of His wisdom, whereby He bestows on men various
measures of virtue, according to Eph. 4:7: "To every one of you [Vulg. :
'us'] is given grace according to the measure of the giving of Christ. "
__________________________________________________________________
Whether all the virtues that are together in one man, are equal?
Objection 1: It would seem that the virtues in one same man are not all
equally intense. For the Apostle says (1 Cor. 7:7): "Everyone hath his
proper gift from God; one after this manner, and another after that. "
Now one gift would not be more proper than another to a man, if God
infused all the virtues equally into each man. Therefore it seems that
the virtues are not all equal in one and the same man.
Objection 2: Further, if all the virtues were equally intense in one
and the same man, it would follow that whoever surpasses another in one
virtue, would surpass him in all the others. But this is clearly not
the case: since various saints are specially praised for different
virtues; e. g. Abraham for faith (Rom. 4), Moses for his meekness (Num.
7:3), Job for his patience (Tob. 2:12). This is why of each Confessor
the Church sings: "There was not found his like in keeping the law of
the most High," [*See Lesson in the Mass Statuit (Dominican Missal)],
since each one was remarkable for some virtue or other. Therefore the
virtues are not all equal in one and the same man.
Objection 3: Further, the more intense a habit is, the greater one's
pleasure and readiness in making use of it. Now experience shows that a
man is more pleased and ready to make use of one virtue than of
another. Therefore the virtues are not all equal in one and the same
man.
On the contrary, Augustine says (De Trin. vi, 4) that "those who are
equal in fortitude are equal in prudence and temperance," and so on.
Now it would not be so, unless all the virtues in one man were equal.
Therefore all virtues are equal in one man.
I answer that, As explained above [1619](A[1]), the comparative
greatness of virtues can be understood in two ways. First, as referring
to their specific nature: and in this way there is no doubt that in a
man one virtue is greater than another, for example, charity, than
faith and hope. Secondly, it may be taken as referring to the degree of
participation by the subject, according as a virtue becomes intense or
remiss in its subject. In this sense all the virtues in one man are
equal with an equality of proportion, in so far as their growth in man
is equal: thus the fingers are unequal in size, but equal in
proportion, since they grow in proportion to one another.
Now the nature of this equality is to be explained in the same way as
the connection of virtues; for equality among virtues is their
connection as to greatness. Now it has been stated above ([1620]Q[65],
A[1]) that a twofold connection of virtues may be assigned. The first
is according to the opinion of those who understood these four virtues
to be four general properties of virtues, each of which is found
together with the other in any matter. In this way virtues cannot be
said to be equal in any matter unless they have all these properties
equal. Augustine alludes to this kind of equality (De Trin. vi, 4) when
he says: "If you say these men are equal in fortitude, but that one is
more prudent than the other; it follows that the fortitude of the
latter is less prudent. Consequently they are not really equal in
fortitude, since the former's fortitude is more prudent. You will find
that this applies to the other virtues if you run over them all in the
same way. "
The other kind of connection among virtues followed the opinion of
those who hold these virtues to have their own proper respective
matters ([1621]Q[65] , AA[1],2). In this way the connection among moral
virtues results from prudence, and, as to the infused virtues, from
charity, and not from the inclination, which is on the part of the
subject, as stated above ([1622]Q[65], A[1]). Accordingly the nature of
the equality among virtues can also be considered on the part of
prudence, in regard to that which is formal in all the moral virtues:
for in one and the same man, so long as his reason has the same degree
of perfection, the mean will be proportionately defined according to
right reason in each matter of virtue.
But in regard to that which is material in the moral virtues, viz. the
inclination to the virtuous act, one may be readier to perform the act
of one virtue, than the act of another virtue, and this either from
nature, or from habituation, or again by the grace of God.
Reply to Objection 1: This saying of the Apostle may be taken to refer
to the gifts of gratuitous grace, which are not common to all, nor are
all of them equal in the one same subject. We might also say that it
refers to the measure of sanctifying grace, by reason of which one man
has all the virtues in greater abundance than another man, on account
of his greater abundance of prudence, or also of charity, in which all
the infused virtues are connected.
Reply to Objection 2: One saint is praised chiefly for one virtue,
another saint for another virtue, on account of his more admirable
readiness for the act of one virtue than for the act of another virtue.
This suffices for the Reply to the Third Objection.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether the moral virtues are better than the intellectual virtues?
Objection 1: It would seem that the moral virtues are better than the
intellectual. Because that which is more necessary, and more lasting,
is better. Now the moral virtues are "more lasting even than the
sciences" (Ethic. i) which are intellectual virtues: and, moreover,
they are more necessary for human life. Therefore they are preferable
to the intellectual virtues.
Objection 2: Further, virtue is defined as "that which makes its
possessor good. " Now man is said to be good in respect of moral virtue,
and art in respect of intellectual virtue, except perhaps in respect of
prudence alone. Therefore moral is better than intellectual virtue.
Objection 3: Further, the end is more excellent than the means. But
according to Ethic. vi, 12, "moral virtue gives right intention of the
end; whereas prudence gives right choice of the means. " Therefore moral
virtue is more excellent than prudence, which is the intellectual
virtue that regards moral matters.
On the contrary, Moral virtue is in that part of the soul which is
rational by participation; while intellectual virtue is in the
essentially rational part, as stated in Ethic. i, 13. Now rational by
essence is more excellent than rational by participation. Therefore
intellectual virtue is better than moral virtue.
I answer that, A thing may be said to be greater or less in two ways:
first, simply; secondly, relatively. For nothing hinders something from
being better simply, e. g. "learning than riches," and yet not better
relatively, i. e. "for one who is in want" [*Aristotle, Topic. iii. ].
Now to consider a thing simply is to consider it in its proper specific
nature. Accordingly, a virtue takes its species from its object, as
explained above ([1623]Q[54], A[2];[1624] Q[60], A[1]). Hence, speaking
simply, that virtue is more excellent, which has the more excellent
object. Now it is evident that the object of the reason is more
excellent than the object of the appetite: since the reason apprehends
things in the universal, while the appetite tends to things themselves,
whose being is restricted to the particular. Consequently, speaking
simply, the intellectual virtues, which perfect the reason, are more
excellent than the moral virtues, which perfect the appetite.
But if we consider virtue in its relation to act, then moral virtue,
which perfects the appetite, whose function it is to move the other
powers to act, as stated above ([1625]Q[9], A[1]), is more excellent.
And since virtue is so called from its being a principle of action, for
it is the perfection of a power, it follows again that the nature of
virtue agrees more with moral than with intellectual virtue, though the
intellectual virtues are more excellent habits, simply speaking.
Reply to Objection 1: The moral virtues are more lasting than the
intellectual virtues, because they are practised in matters pertaining
to the life of the community. Yet it is evident that the objects of the
sciences, which are necessary and invariable, are more lasting than the
objects of moral virtue, which are certain particular matters of
action. That the moral virtues are more necessary for human life,
proves that they are more excellent, not simply, but relatively.
Indeed, the speculative intellectual virtues, from the very fact that
they are not referred to something else, as a useful thing is referred
to an end, are more excellent. The reason for this is that in them we
have a kind of beginning of that happiness which consists in the
knowledge of truth, as stated above ([1626]Q[3], A[6]).
Reply to Objection 2: The reason why man is said to be good simply, in
respect of moral virtue, but not in respect of intellectual virtue, is
because the appetite moves the other powers to their acts, as stated
above ([1627]Q[56], A[3]). Wherefore this argument, too, proves merely
that moral virtue is better relatively.
Reply to Objection 3: Prudence directs the moral virtues not only in
the choice of the means, but also in appointing the end. Now the end of
each moral virtue is to attain the mean in the matter proper to that
virtue; which mean is appointed according to the right ruling of
prudence, as stated in Ethic. ii, 6; vi, 13.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether justice is the chief of the moral virtues?
Objection 1: It would seem that justice is not the chief of the moral
virtues. For it is better to give of one's own than to pay what is due.
Now the former belongs to liberality, the latter to justice. Therefore
liberality is apparently a greater virtue than justice.
Objection 2: Further, the chief quality of a thing is, seemingly, that
in which it is most perfect. Now, according to Jam. 1:4, "Patience hath
a perfect work. " Therefore it would seem that patience is greater than
justice.
Objection 3: Further, "Magnanimity has a great influence on every
virtue," as stated in Ethic. iv, 3. Therefore it magnifies even
justice. Therefore it is greater than justice.
On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Ethic. v, 1) that "justice is
the most excellent of the virtues. "
I answer that, A virtue considered in its species may be greater or
less, either simply or relatively. A virtue is said to be greater
simply, whereby a greater rational good shines forth, as stated above
[1628](A[1]). In this way justice is the most excellent of all the
moral virtues, as being most akin to reason. This is made evident by
considering its subject and its object: its subject, because this is
the will, and the will is the rational appetite, as stated above (Q[8],
A[1]; Q[26], A[1]): its object or matter, because it is about
operations, whereby man is set in order not only in himself, but also
in regard to another. Hence "justice is the most excellent of virtues"
(Ethic. v, 1). Among the other moral virtues, which are about the
passions, the more excellent the matter in which the appetitive
movement is subjected to reason, so much the more does the rational
good shine forth in each. Now in things touching man, the chief of all
is life, on which all other things depend. Consequently fortitude which
subjects the appetitive movement to reason in matters of life and
death, holds the first place among those moral virtues that are about
the passions, but is subordinate to justice. Hence the Philosopher says
(Rhet. 1) that "those virtues must needs be greatest which receive the
most praise: since virtue is a power of doing good. Hence the brave man
and the just man are honored more than others; because the former,"
i. e. fortitude, "is useful in war, and the latter," i. e. justice, "both
in war and in peace. " After fortitude comes temperance, which subjects
the appetite to reason in matters directly relating to life, in the one
individual, or in the one species, viz. in matters of food and of sex.
And so these three virtues, together with prudence, are called
principal virtues, in excellence also.
A virtue is said to be greater relatively, by reason of its helping or
adorning a principal virtue: even as substance is more excellent simply
than accident: and yet relatively some particular accident is more
excellent than substance in so far as it perfects substance in some
accidental mode of being.
Reply to Objection 1: The act of liberality needs to be founded on an
act of justice, for "a man is not liberal in giving, unless he gives of
his own" (Polit. ii, 3). Hence there could be no liberality apart from
justice, which discerns between "meum" and "tuum": whereas justice can
be without liberality. Hence justice is simply greater than liberality,
as being more universal, and as being its foundation: while liberality
is greater relatively since it is an ornament and an addition to
justice.
Reply to Objection 2: Patience is said to have "a perfect work," by
enduring evils, wherein it excludes not only unjust revenge, which is
also excluded by justice; not only hatred, which is also suppressed by
charity; nor only anger, which is calmed by gentleness; but also
inordinate sorrow, which is the root of all the above. Wherefore it is
more perfect and excellent through plucking up the root in this matter.
It is not, however, more perfect than all the other virtues simply.
Because fortitude not only endures trouble without being disturbed, but
also fights against it if necessary. Hence whoever is brave is patient;
but the converse does not hold, for patience is a part of fortitude.
Reply to Objection 3: There can be no magnanimity without the other
virtues, as stated in Ethic. iv, 3. Hence it is compared to them as
their ornament, so that relatively it is greater than all the others,
but not simply.
__________________________________________________________________
Whether wisdom is the greatest of the intellectual virtues?
Objection 1: It would seem that wisdom is not the greatest of the
intellectual virtues. Because the commander is greater than the one
commanded. Now prudence seems to command wisdom, for it is stated in
Ethic. i, 2 that political science, which belongs to prudence (Ethic.
vi, 8), "orders that sciences should be cultivated in states, and to
which of these each individual should devote himself, and to what
extent. " Since, then, wisdom is one of the sciences, it seems that
prudence is greater than wisdom.
Objection 2: Further, it belongs to the nature of virtue to direct man
to happiness: because virtue is "the disposition of a perfect thing to
that which is best," as stated in Phys. vii, text. 17. Now prudence is
"right reason about things to be done," whereby man is brought to
happiness: whereas wisdom takes no notice of human acts, whereby man
attains happiness. Therefore prudence is a greater virtue than wisdom.
Objection 3: Further, the more perfect knowledge is, the greater it
seems to be. Now we can have more perfect knowledge of human affairs,
which are the subject of science, than of Divine things, which are the
object of wisdom, which is the distinction given by Augustine (De Trin.
xii, 14): because Divine things are incomprehensible, according to Job
26:26: "Behold God is great, exceeding our knowledge. " Therefore
science is a greater virtue than wisdom.
Objection 4: Further, knowledge of principles is more excellent than
knowledge of conclusions. But wisdom draws conclusions from
indemonstrable principles which are the object of the virtue of
understanding, even as other sciences do. Therefore understanding is a
greater virtue than wisdom.
On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Ethic. vi, 7) that wisdom is
"the head" among "the intellectual virtues. "
I answer that, As stated above [1629](A[3]), the greatness of a virtue,
as to its species, is taken from its object. Now the object of wisdom
surpasses the objects of all the intellectual virtues: because wisdom
considers the Supreme Cause, which is God, as stated at the beginning
of the Metaphysics. And since it is by the cause that we judge of an
effect, and by the higher cause that we judge of the lower effects;
hence it is that wisdom exercises judgment over all the other
intellectual virtues, directs them all, and is the architect of them
all.
Reply to Objection 1: Since prudence is about human affairs, and wisdom
about the Supreme Cause, it is impossible for prudence to be a greater
virtue than wisdom, "unless," as stated in Ethic. vi, 7, "man were the
greatest thing in the world. " Wherefore we must say, as stated in the
same book (Ethic. vi), that prudence does not command wisdom, but vice
versa: because "the spiritual man judgeth all things; and he himself is
judged by no man" (1 Cor. 2:15). For prudence has no business with
supreme matters which are the object of wisdom: but its command covers
things directed to wisdom, viz. how men are to obtain wisdom. Wherefore
prudence, or political science, is, in this way, the servant of wisdom;
for it leads to wisdom, preparing the way for her, as the doorkeeper
for the king.
Reply to Objection 2: Prudence considers the means of acquiring
happiness, but wisdom considers the very object of happiness, viz. the
Supreme Intelligible. And if indeed the consideration of wisdom were
perfect in respect of its object, there would be perfect happiness in
the act of wisdom: but as, in this life, the act of wisdom is imperfect
in respect of its principal object, which is God, it follows that the
act of wisdom is a beginning or participation of future happiness, so
that wisdom is nearer than prudence to happiness.
Reply to Objection 3: As the Philosopher says (De Anima i, text. 1),
"one knowledge is preferable to another, either because it is about a
higher object, or because it is more certain.
