An artwork that pleases "non sara piu chiara e piu distinta, ma molto piu portara
di novita e di meraviglia," in Discorsi dell'arte poetica e in particolare sopra ilpo- ema eroico, quoted from Tasso, Prosa (Milan, 1969), p.
di novita e di meraviglia," in Discorsi dell'arte poetica e in particolare sopra ilpo- ema eroico, quoted from Tasso, Prosa (Milan, 1969), p.
Niklas Luhmann - Art of the Social System
9. For an overview, see Niels Werber, Literatur als System: Zur Ausdifferen- zierung literarischer Kommunikation (Opladen, 1992).
10. E. g. , in the abundance of moral ambiguities in the self-commenting au-
Notes to Pages 190-91
367
tonographies of Ludwig Tieck's William Lovell, and, of course, in the work's the- oretical reflections.
11. The first quotation is from Lucinde, the second from the essay "Uber Less- ing. " See Friedrich Schlegel, Werke in zwei B'dnden (Berlin, 1980), vol. 2, p. 35, and vol. 1, p. no.
12. "Moralitat ohne Sinn fur Paradoxic ist gemein," states Friedrich Schlegel, ibid. , vol. 1, p. 272.
13. Moreover, one also finds formulations that do not refer to ideals or values and therefore come closer to current notions of balance. See, e. g. , Giovanni Paolo Lomazzo, Idea del Tempio delta Pittura (Milan, 1590), p. 62: "differenze e quella cosa per la quale si discerne, & awerisce l'amicitia & l'inimicitia delle cose. " And on p. 83: "Belezza non e altro che una certa gratia vivace & spirituale, la qual per il raggio divino prima s'infonde ne gl'Angeli in cui si vedeno le figure di qualuna sfera che si chiamano in loro essemplari, & l'ldee; poi passa ne gli an- imi, ove le figure si chiamano ragioni, & notitie; & finalemente nella materia ove si dicono imagini & forme. "
14. In his Erstes Kritisches Wdldchen with reference to examples from antiquity. See Bernhard Suphan, ed. , Herder Sammtliche Werke, vol. 3 (Berlin, 1878), pp. J2ff. (quotation on p. 59).
15. For a historically extensive treatment, see Hans Robert Jauss, ed. , Die nicht mehr schonen Kiinste: Grenzphdnomene des Asthetischen, Poetik und Hermeneutik, vol. 3 (Munich, 1968).
16. See, e. g. , Henri Testelin, Sentiments desplus Habiles Peintres sur la Pratique de h Peinture et la Sculpture (Paris, 1696), pp. 39f.
17. See, e. g. , William Hogarth, The Analysis of Beauty, written with a view of fixing the fluctuating Ideas of Taste (London, 1753; Oxford, 1955), pp. 326? . , 6iff. Hogarth makes the remarkable assumption that the principles of producing
beautiful works (for Hogarth, forms of drawing a line) are not applicable to ugly objects, so that a representation of such objects (although it is admissible) re- quires a deviation from these principles. The "waving line" of beauty is not suited for this purpose (pp. 67f. ). See also the distinction between the drawing (trait) of persons (noble/grossiere) according to their social "condition" in Tes- telin, Sentiments desplus Habiles Peintres, pp. 12,13,17,40.
18. See Gotthold Ephraim Lessing, Laokoon, oder uber die Grenzen der Ma- lerei undPoesie (1766), quoted from Lessings Werke, vol. 3 (Leipzig-Vienna, n. d. ), pp. 1-194.
19. See Friedrich Schlegel, "Vom asthetischen Wert der griechischen Kom- modie," quoted from Werke in zwei B'dnden (Berlin, 1980), vol. 1, pp. 3-14, esp. p. 8, with emphasis on the differentiation and specialization of the code: "Nichts verdient Tadel in einem Kunstwerk als Vergehungen wider die Schon- heit und wider die Darstellung: das HalSliche und das Fehlerhafte. " Note how
368 Notes to Pages 191-96
Schlegel already distinguishes between the figural and the operative component of representation.
20. See Niklas Luhmann, "1st Kunst codierbar? " in Luhmann, Soziologische Aufkldrung vol. 3 (Opladen, 1981), pp. 245-66.
21. Claiming that this is possible because of prior aesthetic experiences with artworks does litde to salvage the terminology. Especially for people, this claim is dubious. (In fact, the opposite might be so: experience with artworks helps recognize the beauty in ugly people. ) Besides, this subterfuge offers no clue as to what exactly enables works of art to serve as a paradigm of beauty.
22. For Kant, this seems to be evident: "Man kann uberhaupt Schonheit (Sie mag Natur- oder Kunstschonheit sein) den Ausdruck asthetischer Ideen nennen; nur dafi in der schonen Kunst diese Idee durch einen Begriff vom Objekt veran- lafit werden muS" (Kritik der Urteilskra. fi, ? 51). Yet soon thereafter, Kant talks about the beauty of die word, of gesture, and of tones (articulation, gesticula- tion, and modulation).
23. See, e. g. , Francis Hutcheson, An Inquiry Concerning Beauty, Order, Har- mony, Design, Treatise I of his Inquiry into the Original ofOur Ideas ofBeauty and Virtue (1725; 4th ed. , 1738; critical ed. The Hague, 1973), ? 4, II, p. 55.
24. Schiller, e. g. , grounds the unity of the idea of beauty in the fact that there can be only one equilibrium of reality and form. See Uber die asthetische Erzie- hung des Menschen in einer Reihe von Briefen, quoted from Schiller, Samtliche
Werke, vol. 5 (Munich, 1967), p. 619. See also Karl Wilhelm Ferdinand Solger, Vorlesungen uber Asthetik, ed. Karl Wilhelm Ludwig Heyse (Leipzig, 1829; rpt.
Darmstadt, 1973), esp. pp. 47ff.
25. As when August Wilhelm Schlegel writes in Die Kunstlehre (vol. 1 of the
Vorlesungen uber schbne Literatur undKunst): "Das Schone ist eine symbolische Darstellung des Unendlichen" (quoted from Kritische Schrifien undBriefe, vol. 2 [Stuttgart, 1963], p. 81).
26. See Jean Paul, Vorschule der Asthetik, quoted from Werke, vol. 5 (Munich, 1963), p. 43: "Schonheit sei, wie es einen Zirkel der Logik gibt, der Zirkel der Phantasie, weil der Kreis die reichste, einfachste, unerschopflichste, leichtfafi- lichste Figur ist; aber der wirkliche Zirkel ist ja selber eine Schonheit, und so wiirde die Definition (wie leider jede) ein logischer. "
27. Parsons employs this formulation in his theory of symbolically generalized media of exchange.
28. See Jacques Derrida, OfGrammatology, trans. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak (Baltimore, 1974).
29. Michel Serres, Le Parasite (Paris, 1980).
30. SeeMaryDouglas,PurityandDanger:AnAnalysisofConceptsofPollution and Taboo (Harmondsworth, Middlesex, 1970).
31. A remarkable example is the manuscript, available only as a copy, of The Codex Nuttall: A Picture ManuscriptfromAncient Mexico, ed. ZeliaNuttall (rpt.
Notes to Pages 196-99 369
New York, 1975). Examples of this sort illustrate the effects of evolution. Even though the representations all focus on the same thing, there is a diversification of species, a wealth of forms that depends on cultural tradition and is not im- mediately intelligible today.
32. This is expressed explicidy in the above-mentioned Codex Nuttall but also more indirecdy in the Greek world of heroes and demigods, whose significance rested primarily on the fact that the aristocracy traced its origins to them.
33. See Plato, Sophistes, 253 D-E.
34. Ibid. , D, the first lines.
35. The first example is techne tes grammatikes, ibid. , 253 A.
36. See Joan Marie Lechner, Renaissance Concepts of the Commonplace (New
York, 1962; rpt. Westport, Conn. , 1974). Even in the seventeenth century, one still found statements such as: "reasons urging [passions, N. L. ] proceed from solid amplifications, amplifications are gathered from common places, common places fit for oratorical persuasion concern a part of Rhetorick called Invention. " See Thomas Wright, The Passions of the Minde in Generall (1604; enlarged ed. London, 1630), p. 185.
37. See Boileau, who takes up the ancient distinction between amplification and proof in his translation of Longinus. For amplification ("ne sert qu'a esten- dre et a exagerer"), see Nicolas Boileau-Despr^aux, Traiti du Sublime, quoted from CEuvres (Paris, 1713), pp. 593-692, 63iff. According to Thomas Sprat, the Royal Society of London for the Improving of Natural Knowledge made a deci- sive move "to reject all the amplifications, digressions and swellings of style" (Sprat, The History of the Royal Society of London . . . [London, 1667; rpt. Lon- don, 1966], p. 113).
38. See Kant, Kritik der Urteilskra. fi, Intro. VI. (Not accidentally, this remark occurs in the context of investigations that aspire to an aesthetics. )
39. See Sir Philip Sidney, The Defense of Poetry (1595; Lincoln, Nebr. , 1970), p. 12. Soon thereafter, diis seems to have become the general opinion. See, e. g. , Jonathan Richardson, A Discourse on the Dignity, Certainty, Pleasure, and Advan- tage of the Science ofa Connoisseur (1719), quoted from The Works (London, 1773; rpt. Hildesheim, 1969), pp. 241-346 (247ff. ).
40. In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, such publications occupied an important place, especially in the realm of painting. For examples, see Christo- foro Sorte, Osservazioni nella pittura (1580), quoted from Paola Barocchi, ed. ,
Trattati d'arte del cinquecento, vol. 1 (Bari, i960), pp. 271-301; or, more exten- sively, Giovanni Paolo Lomazzo, Trattato dell'arte, della Pittura, Scultura ed ar- chitettura, 3 vols. (1584; Rome, 1844).
41. See Gotthard Giinther, "Die historische Kategorie des Neuen," in Giin- ther, Beitrage zur Grundlegung einer operationsfdhigen Dialektik (Hamburg, 1980), vol. 3, pp. 183-210.
42. On "ballads" and mystery stories motivated by executions, see esp. Len-
37Q Notes to Pages ipp-203
nardj. Davis, Factual Fictions: The Origins of the English Novel (NewYork, 1983), pp. 42ff.
43. See Sidney, The Defense of Poetry, pp. i3ff.
44. Raising this issue assumed that the Aristotelian concept of nature was no longer intelligible and that the text of the Poetics was used merely for purposes of quotation and illustration.
45. See Baxter Hathaway, Marvels and Commonplaces: Renaissance Literary Criticism (New York, 1968), pp. i58ff. The context is the Italian discussion of classical and contemporary texts, which was later taken up in France and Eng- land. Torquato Tasso still emphasizes both intelligibility and astonishing novelty.
An artwork that pleases "non sara piu chiara e piu distinta, ma molto piu portara
di novita e di meraviglia," in Discorsi dell'arte poetica e in particolare sopra ilpo- ema eroico, quoted from Tasso, Prosa (Milan, 1969), p. 388. One can already dis- cern the new tendency to foreground novelty.
46. See (Pseudo) Cicero, Ad Herennium, III, XXII, quoted from The Loeb Classical Library edition (Cambridge, Mass. , 1968), pp. 2i8ff. On subsequent de- velopments, see Paolo Rossi, "La costruzione delle immagini nei trattati di memoria artificiale del Rinascimento," in Umanesimo e simbolismo, Archivio di filosofia (1958), pp. 161-78; Cesare Vasoli, "Umanesimo e Simbologia nei primi scritti Lulliani e mnemotechnici del Bruno," ibid. , pp. 251-304. See also Frances A. Yates, The Art of Memory (Chicago, 1966).
47. This is indeed noticed and emphasized--even by Jonathan Richardson, A Discourse on the Dignity, p. 270: "nor can any man pronounce upon the pleasure of another"--despite the author's concern with the solid principles of a science of expertise as a precondition of pleasure.
48. O n the corresponding notion of time, see Chapter 3, section III, above.
49. Another, equally transitory solution might have been a sophisticated tech- nique for covering over the traces of the rules on which an artwork was based and subsequently deflecting the admiration to the successful deception. Rooted in the older rhetorical tradition, this notion of art was especially important for the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. See Gerhard Schroder, Logos und List (Konigsstein/Ts. , 1985).
50. It is difficult to appreciate Hogarth's opinion that ugly objects defy repre- sentation in accordance with the recipe for beauty (curved lines): "The ugliness of the toad, the hug, the bear and the spider are totally void of this waving-line. " See Hogarth, The Analysis of Beauty, pp. 66f.
51. See Arthur C. Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace: A Philosophy of Art (Cambridge, Mass. , 1981). Danto must have recourse to contrived examples in order to demonstrate complete indistinguishability. If an artist were to create two identical (indistinguishable) objects without marking one as the copy of the other, such a program could communicate only one thing: that this is the program.
Notes to Pages 203-8
37i
52. See the complex analysis of "without" as a condition for beauty in Jacques Derrick, The Truth in Painting, trans. Geoff Bennington and Ian McLeod (Chi- cago, 1987), pp. 83ff.
53. The twentieth letter of Schiller, Briefe iiber die dsthetische Erziehung des Menschen, p. 634 n.
54. Schiller, "Notwendige Grenzen beim Gebrauch schoner Formen," ibid. , p. 688.
55. As we note in passing, this insight dissolves the traditional nexus between freedom and power in the political context and the nexus between freedom and hierarchy in the social context, which does not mean that cognition (in the sense of exploring a space for decisions) cannot be influenced by power or by hierar- chical positions.
56. Robert Glanville, Objekte (Berlin, 1988), claims that this is true for all ob- jects. This is not easy to see. It is remarkable, however, that this claim is made by an architect.
57. See, e. g. , Karl Philipp Moritz, "Die metaphysische Schonheitslinie," in Schriften zur Asthetik und Poetik (Tubingen, 1962), pp. 151-57 (157): "Das Ge- horige weglassen [or rather: das gehorige Weglassen, N. L. ], ist also eigentlich das wahre Wesen der Kunst, die mehr negativ, als positiv zu Werke gehen mufi, wenn sie gefallen soil. " One can trace this view into our own century, e. g. , to Mondrian.
58. Explicitly, August Wilhelm Schlegel, Die Kunstlehre (Pt. 1 of the lectures on literature and art), quoted from Kritische Schriften und Briefe, vol. 2 (Stutt- gart, 1963), p. 71. See also Chapter 4, section VII, above.
59. On the separation of these distinctions in a sociotheoretical context, see
also Niklas Luhmann, "Das Moderne der modernen Gesellschaft," in Luhmann, 2
Beobachtungen der Moderne (Opladen, 1992), pp. 11-49 ( 5ff-); trans, as "Moder- nity in Contemporary Society," in Luhmann, Observations on Modernity, trans. William Whobrey (Stanford, Calif, 1998), pp. 1^21 (9ff. )
60. On his version of the reentry paradox, which duplicates the framing of the artwork within the work itself and thereby shows that this is the work's own pro- gram, see David Roberts, "The Paradox of Form: Literature and Self-Reference," Poetics 21 (1992): 75-91; "The form within the form frames the enclosing form. "
61. Johann Joachim Winckelmann, Geschichte der Kunst des Altertums {vj6y- 1768), quoted from Sdmtliche Werke, vols. 3-6 (1825; rpt. Osnabriick, 1965).
62. For an elaboration of this point, see Niklas Luhmann, "Das Kunstwerk und die Selbstreproduktion der Kunst," in Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht and K. Lud- wig Pfeiffer, eds. , Stil: Geschichten und Funktionen eines kulturwissenschaftlichen Diskurselements (Frankfurt, 1986), pp. 620-72.
63. Henri Focillon, The Life of Forms in Art (New York, 1992), p. 47.
64. The Church of the Holy Spirit, located in front of the train station in
372 Notes to Pages 208-1$
Bern, combines in a remarkable manner rococo elements with neoclassical stylis- tic forms--of course, without following a postmodern manner of construction.
65. See Chapter 3, section VII, above.
66. August Wilhelm Schlegel recognizes this problem and solves it via die no- tion of the "perfection" of the individual work (see Die Kunstlehre, p. 20), but the problem undergoes a modification that invites consideration of national dis- tinctions. "Sonst aber mufi jedes Kunstwerk aus seinem Standpunkte betrachtet werden; es braucht nicht ein absolut Hochstes zu erreichen, es ist vollendet, wenn es ein Hochstes in seiner Art, in seiner Sphare, seiner Welt ist; und so erk- lart sich wie es zugleich ein Glied in einer unendlichen Reihe von Fortschritten, und dennoch an und fiir sich befriedigend und selbststandig sein kann. " How- ever, Schlegel's inference of an infinite progress for the notion of perfection does, to put it mildly, beg the question.
67. Not accidentally in the realm of architecture and radiating from it. One thinks of Viollet-le-Duc, of the restoration of cathedrals, and of the rebuilding of Carcassonne.
68. Exceptions are ironic or strangely rendered stylistic quotations such as those that can be found in the music of Stravinsky or Schnittke.
? 6
1. See, e. g. , the distinction beau rialIbeau relatif'm Denis Diderot, Traiti du beau, quoted from CEuvres, Plelade ed. (Paris, 1951), pp. 1105-42 (ii27ff).
2. See Georg Kauffmann, Die Entstehung der Kunstgeschichte im ip. Jahrhun- dert (Opladen, 1993).
3. Comparing historiography and poetry, Sir Philip Sidney speaks of "old moth-eaten records," The Defense ofPoetry (1595; Lincoln, Nebr. , 1970), p. 15. 4. Herbert Spencer, "What Is Social Evolution? " The Nineteenth Century 44
(1898): 348-58 (353). For a more detailed account, see the chapters on "The Law of Evolution," in Herbert Spencer, First Principles, 5th ed. (London, 1887), pp. 307*1
5. See several of the contributions in Revue internationale de systemique 7, no. 5 (1993)-
6. See Marion Blute, "Sociocultural Evolutionism: An Untried Theory," Be- havioral Science 24 (1979): 46-59. There are counterexamples, as well, thanks to the numerous contributions of Donald T. Campbell.
7. On this version of the problem, see Magoroh Maruyama, "Postscript to the Second Cybernetics," American Scientist 51 (1963): 250-56.
8. See Niklas Luhmann, "The Paradox of System Differentiation and the Evolution of Society," in Jeffrey C. Alexander and Paul Colomy, eds. , Differenti-
ation Theory and Social Change: Comparative and Historical Perspectives (New
Notes to Pages 215-19
373
York, 1990), pp. 409-40; Niklas Luhmann and Raffaele De Giorgi, Teoria della societa (Milan, 1992), pp. 169ft".
9. On Schelling's significance in developing this line of questioning, see Wil- helm G. Jacobs, "Geschichte und Kunst in Schellings 'System des tranzscenden- talen Idealismus,'" in Walter Jaeschke and Helmut Holzhey, eds. , Friiher Idealis- mus und Friihromantik: Der Streit um die Grundlagen der Asthetik (IJ9$-I8O$) (Hamburg, 1990), pp. 201-13. Schelling only arrived at another teleology of his- tory that entailed, apart from a cosmopolitan society of constitutional states (peace), an epiphany of art that unfolds its unique paradox of a both conscious and unconscious life in history.
10. See Chapter 4, sections IVfE, above.
n . Friedrich Schlegel ascertains: "und gewifi ist die Arabeske [understood as "diese kiinstlich geordnete Verwirrung, diese reizende Symmetric von Wider- spriichen, dieser wunderbare ewige Wechsel von Enthusiasmus und Ironie"] die alteste und urspriinglichste Form der menschlichen Fantasie" {Gesprdchtiberdie Poesie, quoted from Werke in zwei Bdnden [Berlin, 1980], vol. 2, p. 164). For de- tailed evidence, see also Franz Boas, Primitive Art (Oslo, 1927; New York, 1955).
12. Ernst Gombrich's important monograph Ornament und Kunst: Schmuck- trieb und Ordnungssinn in der Psychologie des dekorativen Schaffens (Stuttgart, 1982) contains a wealth of material from all ages, but it is ordered in view of fac- tual concerns and does not claim to offer a history of the ornament and its rela- tionship to the evolution of art. For a historical account that illustrates how the European development of the ornament profited from its subordination to ar- chitectural and structural innovations, and later to specifically artistic stylistic in- ventions, see Joan Evans, Pattern: A Study of Ornament in Western Europe from 1180 to ipoo, 2 vols. (1931; rpt. New York, 1975). For the beginnings of this divi- sion in the construction of gothic cathedrals, see also Otto von Simson, The Gothic Cathedral: The Origins of Gothic Architecture and the Medieval Concept of Order (New York, 1965), e. g. , p. 5: "Here ornamentation is entirely subordinated to the pattern produced by the structural members, the vault ribs and support- ing shafts; the aesthetic system is determined by these. "
13. See Chapter 3, n. 40, above.
14. See, e. g. , Michel Angelo Biondo, Von der hochedlen Malerei (1547; German trans. Vienna, 1873; rpt. Osnabriick, 1970), pp. 24f, 28ff.
15. Biondo believes that beauty appears on the outside of the painted objects (in the drawing? but Biondo speaks of composition); see ibid. , p. 30.
16. See Wolfgang Kemp, "Disegno: Beitrage zur Geschichte des Begriffs zwis- chen 1547 und 1607," Marburger Jahrbuch fiir Kunstwissenschafi 19 (1974), pp. 219-40.
17. First ed. (Venice, 1587), quoted from Torquato Tasso, Prosa (Milan, 1969), p. 349. The formulation "ed vestirla ultimamente con que' piu esquisiti orna-
Notes to Pages 219-20
374
menti" clearly shows ambivalence toward the ornament: on the one hand, it earns rhetorical praise; on the other hand, it is marginalized as a decoration after the fact.
18. Tasso, Discorso terzo, pp. 392ff.
19. See Chapter 3, section IV, above.
20. For detailed evidence, see Evans, Pattern. The difficulty of distinguishing
such external suggestions from stylistic developments within the art system is ob- vious, and it proves once more how artificial the separation between art and or- nament really is.
21. Jacques Derrida has dealt with the "parergon" in relation to the "ergon" with reference to Kant's Third Critique in The Truth in Painting, trans. Geoff Bennington and Ian McLeod (Chicago, 1987).
22. See Francis Hutcheson, An Inquiry Concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony, Design, Treatise I of his Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas ofBeauty and Virtue (1725; 4th ed. , 1738; critical ed. The Hague, 1973), ? 1, III, pp. 38f.
23. See section IV of this chapter.
24. Hutcheson, Inquiry, ? 2, III, p. 40. In the theory of art, such formulas were already common in the sixteenth century, i.
